12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Atheism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Theism</strong> 47<br />

wager. Pascal’s Wager will be discussed in the next section. The argument<br />

of the wager purports to prove that one should by a sort of brain washing,<br />

going to masses, using holy water, <strong>and</strong> so on, induce belief in the Catholic<br />

religion. Pascal, as already a believer, would probably disapprove of the<br />

term ‘brainwashing’. It is not clear whether he would regard the acquisition<br />

of belief after immersing oneself in Catholic practices as explicable<br />

naturalistically. He might have held that these practices somehow attract<br />

the grace of God. To the sceptic of course the whole thing must initially<br />

appear as a sort of brainwashing. Such psychological mechanisms are indeed<br />

possible. One might cultivate the company of conservatively religious persons,<br />

avoid reading books such as Bertr<strong>and</strong> Russell’s Why I am not a Christian,<br />

83 <strong>and</strong> confine one’s philosophical reading to St Thomas Aquinas, or<br />

better still avoid philosophical reading altogether <strong>and</strong> stick to electronics<br />

or pure mathematics, or other theologically neutral subject matter, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

practical activities. Whether it would be rational to submit to such nonrational<br />

processes is another matter. To decide this we must wait on our<br />

discussion of the wager.<br />

10 Pascal’s Wager<br />

Pascal, the important seventeenth-century mathematician <strong>and</strong> physicist,<br />

became an adherent of the austere Jansenist group of Catholics who were<br />

rivals of the more worldly Jesuits. Pascal held that the existence of God could<br />

not be proved by reason. (Later, the First Vatican Council was to condemn<br />

this opinion as a heresy.) He implicitly conflated belief in God with belief in<br />

the Catholic religion, including its doctrine about bliss in heaven <strong>and</strong> infinite<br />

torment in hell. So for him the only two ‘living options’, as William James<br />

called them, 84 were Catholicism on the one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> atheism on the other<br />

h<strong>and</strong>. For example, he would not think of Islam <strong>and</strong> a Muslim would not<br />

think of Catholicism. Moreover, there are other options, though not ones that<br />

Pascal would have considered. Nevertheless in evaluating Pascal’s argument<br />

we must consider other options.<br />

Still, let us for the moment pretend that Pascal’s two options are the<br />

only ones <strong>and</strong> follow his argument which can be put simply as follows.<br />

Pascal argued that Catholicism has a non-zero probability. He concedes that<br />

it is possible that one might have many pleasures in our earthly life which<br />

would be lost to us if we embraced a strict religious life. However, Pascal<br />

points out that such happiness could only be finite. Even the smallest finite<br />

probability of infinite torment in hell would outweigh it, since it would give<br />

an infinitely negative ‘expected utility’ (to use a present day terminology).<br />

The product of an infinite unhappiness with even the smallest non-zero

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!