12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

50 J.J.C. Smart<br />

take. So despite his reservation about Pascal his own attitude was not really so<br />

different. Indeed James held that if we take the leap of faith belief will follow.<br />

(Or indeed not so much follow as be there already, given James’s largely<br />

behaviourist theory of belief.) It may be that James’s pragmatism was a source<br />

of his view in ‘The Will to Believe’ since the notion of working in practice in<br />

the sense of leading to a worthwhile life could easily have been confused in<br />

his mind with verification of a hypothesis by observation. Explicitly, I think,<br />

he did distinguish the two things but even within this one essay he was not<br />

always a very self-consistent writer, <strong>and</strong> this makes him hard to interpret. His<br />

views are probably not as outrageous as a superficial account of them might<br />

suggest. Be that as it may, his ‘Will to Believe’ does suggest something like<br />

the decision to brainwash oneself.<br />

Religious apologists do sometimes defend a leap of faith by saying that<br />

science itself depends on a giant leap of faith. They might point out that<br />

since Hume raised the philosophical problem of induction it has appeared<br />

that we have no reason to believe that the future will be like the past. According<br />

to Hume laws of nature are mere regularities whose continuance in the<br />

future cannot be justified by reason. Nowadays we might put it by saying<br />

that hypotheses are always underdetermined by observation. The apologists<br />

could seek a similarity between attempted pragmatic justifications of induction<br />

(or scientific method) <strong>and</strong> the religious pragmatism of William James.<br />

These attempt to show that if any method of predicting the future works<br />

then induction (the scientific method) works. (Of course science is concerned<br />

not only with prediction but with explanation <strong>and</strong> with theoretical knowledge,<br />

<strong>and</strong> there is a question of whether the pragmatic vindication of induction<br />

could be taken beyond vindicating it as a mere prediction device.) There<br />

does nevertheless seem to be an important difference. Many people have no<br />

difficulty in living without religious belief but no philosophical sceptic about<br />

induction could continue to live if he or she really believed this scepticism.<br />

The spectacular advances of science, <strong>and</strong> its applications to technology <strong>and</strong> to<br />

medicine, would seem to me to make impossible a really sincere philosophical<br />

scepticism about scientific method. Even fundamentalist Protestant sects in<br />

the USA who promulgate a two-thous<strong>and</strong>-year-old view of the universe do<br />

so unblushingly with the aid of modern electronics of radio <strong>and</strong> television<br />

<strong>and</strong> their medical missionaries make use of the most sophisticated biological<br />

techniques of contemporary medicine. The religious leap of faith is therefore<br />

a leap additional to that of the scientist, not an alternative to it. I conjecture<br />

that the sort of religious apologist that I am considering here would have to<br />

be an instrumentalist in the philosophy of science, <strong>and</strong> a realist in theology.<br />

It is an uncomfortable position. By contrast an atheist who was a scientific<br />

realist need not be an instrumentalist about theological statements: he or she<br />

might simply give them the truth value ‘false’.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!