12.07.2013 Views

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

Atheism and Theism JJ Haldane - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

42 J.J.C. Smart<br />

the theist in the search for some analogue of God’s necessity in that of mathematical<br />

existence.<br />

Probably, therefore, the theist’s best bet might after all be to try to defend<br />

the old fashioned form of mathematical Platonism, with its direct intuitions<br />

of a super-sensible reality (universals), which exist eternally <strong>and</strong> in some sense<br />

necessarily. If this sense of ‘necessarily’ could be made intelligible then God<br />

might be said to exist necessarily in this sense. We are led into obscurities <strong>and</strong><br />

it is, as I have said, hard to fit Platonic intuitions into modern epistemology<br />

<strong>and</strong> neurobiology.<br />

When all is said, however, it might be best for the theist to say simply<br />

‘God exists necessarily’ in the way that the number 23 does. Would this be<br />

a sort of polytheism with many necessary beings? Or would 23 be somehow<br />

part of God? I leave this question to theologians. The atheist will feel well<br />

relieved of these intractable problems.<br />

Eternity <strong>and</strong> Sempiternity<br />

In discussing the cosmological argument I took it that Aquinas was at his<br />

best in thinking of God as eternal, in the sense of not being in time at all. In<br />

this way the existence of God would be said to explain the existence of the<br />

whole space–time world (as we think of it) without being an efficient cause at<br />

the first moment of the universe’s existence, a concept which has no clear<br />

sense in modern cosmology. As I noted, the universe can have a finite past<br />

<strong>and</strong> yet have no unique first moment. Furthermore there is no unitary time.<br />

The special theory of relativity tells us that there is no preferred set of axes in<br />

Minkowski space. Still, perhaps a preferred set could be got by going outside<br />

the theory, e.g. in preferring space–time axes with respect to which the cosmic<br />

background radiation is equal in all directions. Even so, because of the<br />

expansion of the universe, these local times would lie in different space–time<br />

directions from galaxy to galaxy. Also time-like world lines get bent up in<br />

black holes (as at the beginning of the universe) <strong>and</strong> black holes may possibly<br />

spawn baby universes with their own different space–times. We should therefore<br />

be cautious about talking of God as in time, sempiternal not eternal. In<br />

what time would a sempiternal God be sempiternal in? These considerations<br />

reinforce, in my mind at least, the interpretation of God’s eternity as atemporal<br />

rather than sempiternal. In what follows I shall use ‘eternal’ in this atemporal<br />

sense <strong>and</strong> shall contrast eternity with sempiternity.<br />

William <strong>and</strong> Martha Kneale have explored the issue of eternity versus<br />

sempiternity in two scholarly <strong>and</strong> instructive papers. 80 They bring out the<br />

tensions in Aquinas’s thought. On the one h<strong>and</strong> Aquinas had a classically<br />

inspired preference for the ‘eternal’ conception of God, which William Kneale<br />

traces back to Parmenides <strong>and</strong> Plato, but not to Aristotle, who was on the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!