26.11.2012 Views

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

167<br />

– It is unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r dative clitics in French require [+person] licensing in<br />

<strong>the</strong> same manner that accusative clitics do in <strong>the</strong> PCC. For datives visible<br />

to <strong>the</strong> PCC in Icel<strong>and</strong>ic, some Case-like need has been posited to render<br />

<strong>the</strong>m visible to A-movement (Chomsky 2000a, cf. Belletti <strong>and</strong> Rizzi 1988,<br />

Freidin <strong>and</strong> Sprouse 1991, Yoon 1996).<br />

These properties <strong>of</strong> datives have been explored in different ways in <strong>the</strong><br />

Agree/Case approach. On one, datives create <strong>the</strong> PCC simply because <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

visible to A-movement, not because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir phi-<strong>features</strong>. Baker (2008: 3.3) develops<br />

such a proposal. He posits that Agree for [+person] requires <strong>the</strong> spec-head<br />

configuration, for instance [Spec, TNOM] in Icel<strong>and</strong>ic. Applicative arguments, including<br />

datives, A-move to <strong>the</strong> specifier <strong>of</strong> T/v. This prevents nominatives from<br />

doing so, <strong>and</strong> thus Agree for [+person]. Better underst<strong>and</strong>ing is needed <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> differences<br />

between languages like Icel<strong>and</strong>ic <strong>and</strong> Basque, since only in <strong>the</strong> former do<br />

datives undergo A-movement to become subjects, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> person agreement with<br />

apparently low nominatives as in (254) that casts doubt on <strong>the</strong> premise. 122<br />

On an alternative view, that <strong>of</strong> Anagnostopoulou (2003) <strong>and</strong> related work, datives<br />

block [+person] Agree/Case relationships through <strong>the</strong>ir own phi-<strong>features</strong>.<br />

The analysis partly inspires itself from applicative objects that are plain DPs, as in<br />

English or Mohawk. These are simply treated as <strong>the</strong> goals <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Agree/Case system<br />

for all purposes <strong>and</strong> prevent it from reaching a lower object, as in (260). The<br />

applicative argument in (260) controls agreement, gets accusative, <strong>and</strong> raises to<br />

[Spec, TP], while <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me is licensed differently. English is uninformative on<br />

this point, <strong>and</strong> probably uses inherent Case or a null preposition (Larson 1988, Pesetsky<br />

1995, Baker 1997, Anagnostopoulou 2001; cf. Bittner <strong>and</strong> Hale 1996: 18).<br />

Mohawk is more revealing. The <strong>the</strong>me must incorporate, <strong>and</strong> incorporation only<br />

licenses inanimates (Baker 1996: 5.3, Ormazabal <strong>and</strong> Romero 1998).<br />

(260) a. She showed <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> cake. (active)<br />

b. They were shown <strong>the</strong> cake. (passive)<br />

Although applicative datives do not control agreement or get overt accusative,<br />

unlike applicative DPs, Anagnostopoulou (2003: 5.4.2) proposes that <strong>the</strong>y never-<br />

139f.), along with unclear 'facilitation' effects <strong>of</strong> a nonagreeing dative on agreement across it (for<br />

Icel<strong>and</strong>ic, see Holmberg <strong>and</strong> Hróarsdóttir 2003: 1001, Sigurðsson <strong>and</strong> Holmberg 2008; for<br />

Basque, Etxepare 2005, Preminger 2009; for Greek, Anagnostopoulou 2003: 202).<br />

122 The evaluation <strong>of</strong> Baker's proposal must include various inversion constructions with low<br />

subjects. In English, locative inversion seems to place <strong>the</strong> fronted PP in an A-position (Bresnan<br />

1994, Collins 1997, Culicover <strong>and</strong> Levine 2001) <strong>and</strong> resist all nominative pronouns (Bresnan<br />

1994: 86). Some inversions do show <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> person agreement specifically (on French,<br />

see Bonami <strong>and</strong> Godard 2001, Rezac 2004a: chapter 5, 2010b; cf. Chomsky 2000a: 149 note 90,<br />

Schütze 1997: 4.1.6). O<strong>the</strong>rs do not, as Icel<strong>and</strong>ic (254) or postverbal subjects in Czech, not to be<br />

simply set aside by assuming that <strong>the</strong> 1 st /2 nd person is really in [Spec, TP] (Baker 2008: 89 note<br />

17), unless it can be shown that it licenses elements like floating quantifiers (Rezac 2010b).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!