26.11.2012 Views

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

70<br />

more clearly syntactic in some systems. There is great potential for enriching <strong>the</strong><br />

set <strong>of</strong> syntactic correlates <strong>of</strong> PH-interactions. 42<br />

3.3 Theories <strong>of</strong> PH-interactions<br />

Syntactic correlates <strong>of</strong> EA-O PH-interactions demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> interactions<br />

play a role in deciding which syntactic structures are grammatical. Most analyses<br />

conclude that syntax accesses <strong>the</strong> necessary distinctions among phi-<strong>features</strong>, for<br />

instance to move 1 st /2 nd person to a different position than 3 rd . However, it remains<br />

analytically possible that PH-interactions only filter syntactic structures without<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves being syntactic. These options <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir limits are discussed in this<br />

section, leading to <strong>the</strong> more robust evidence <strong>of</strong> Arizona Tewa in <strong>the</strong> next.<br />

A common implementation <strong>of</strong> PH-interactions envisages that <strong>the</strong> clause is partitioned<br />

into regions dedicated to a particular interpretation. 43 The person hierarchy<br />

is a hierarchy <strong>of</strong> layers in <strong>the</strong> non<strong>the</strong>matic region <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> clause, each defined<br />

by a phi-feature class. For a 1/2 > 3 hierarchy, <strong>the</strong>re would be a 1 st /2 nd person layer<br />

above one for 3 rd person as in (97), for instance Déchaine's (1999) PersonP above<br />

NumberP or Bianchi's (2006) Speech Act Participants Phrase SAPP above 3 rd person<br />

Phrase 3P. The layers may be suitable elaborated, for instance 2 > 1 ><br />

3.PROX > 3.OBV for Algonquian.<br />

(97) a. [PersonP 1/2:EA [NumberP … tEA … 3:O …]] direct (1/2→3)<br />

b. [PersonP 1/2:O [NumberP … 3:EA … tO …]] inverse (3→1/2)<br />

Arguments map to <strong>the</strong> appropriate layers by movement. 1 st person moves to<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1 st /2 nd person layer whe<strong>the</strong>r EA or O, 3 rd person stays lower. Only EA <strong>and</strong> O<br />

are affected, since DPs in PPs are typically inaccessible to <strong>the</strong> relevant clausal (A-<br />

42 For instance, in Movima, Haude (2006: 7.1-5), <strong>the</strong> winner <strong>of</strong> EA-O PH interaction must be<br />

overtly expressed <strong>and</strong> enclitic to <strong>the</strong> verb, with direct/inverse verbal markers indicating whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

it is <strong>the</strong> EA or <strong>the</strong> O, according to <strong>the</strong> hierarchy 1SG > 1INCL/EXCL > 2SG > 2PL > 3 human ><br />

3 non-human. This constraint ranges over both enclitics <strong>and</strong> full 3 rd person DPs, making it appear<br />

syntactic ra<strong>the</strong>r than morphological. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> generalization has exceptions where <strong>the</strong> 2 nd<br />

person in 1↔2 combinations is enclitic, but <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> 1 st person must still obey <strong>the</strong> constraint by<br />

being overt as a free pronoun, also suggesting a generalization going beyond clitics (Haude 2006:<br />

278). In syntactic terms, <strong>the</strong> winner <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> PH-interaction might move to a designated subjecthood<br />

position, which must be overt <strong>and</strong> control enclisis. Fascinating PH-interactions that fail to<br />

be clearly syntactic include Lakämper <strong>and</strong> Wunderlich (1998) for Quechua, <strong>and</strong> Dixon (2000),<br />

Farell (2005: 77ff.) for Jarawara; an example <strong>of</strong> a PH-interaction that has turned out to be spurious<br />

is Nichols' (1998: chapter 2) reanalysis <strong>of</strong> Zuni from Nichols (1996), Albizu (1997b).<br />

43 For o<strong>the</strong>r types <strong>of</strong> syntactic <strong>the</strong>ories where phi-feature distinctions condition movement, see<br />

Laka (1993a), Johns (1996), Nash (1997), Hale (2001), Béjar (2003), Béjar <strong>and</strong> Rezac (2009),<br />

Baker (2008). Reference to phi-<strong>features</strong> may be under o<strong>the</strong>r terms. For Bruening (2001: 2.4.5),<br />

A-movement occurs through <strong>the</strong> feature [+P], but <strong>the</strong> 1 st /2 nd -3 rd person distinction governs <strong>the</strong><br />

distribution <strong>of</strong> [+P]: 1 st /2 nd person is inherently [+P], a 3 rd person must not be [+P] if coargument<br />

<strong>of</strong> 1 st /2 nd person, while for two 3 rd person coarguments one <strong>and</strong> one only is [+P].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!