26.11.2012 Views

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

20<br />

b. Where are <strong>the</strong> boysi whoi Tom think(s) ti Dick believe(s) ti Harry expect(s)<br />

ti to be late?<br />

(Boston English, Kimball <strong>and</strong> Aissen 1971: 246)<br />

The issues raised by agreement with <strong>the</strong> target's nonarguments are brought to<br />

a point by (24), discussed in chapter 2. In Spanish <strong>the</strong> 3 rd person masculine accusative<br />

clitic is singular lo <strong>and</strong> plural los, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 3 rd person dative clitic is singular<br />

le <strong>and</strong> plural les. However when 3PL.DAT <strong>and</strong> 3SG.ACC are combined in <strong>the</strong><br />

same clitic cluster, <strong>the</strong> result is not <strong>the</strong> transparent les lo. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, les is replaced by<br />

<strong>the</strong> default clitic se, <strong>and</strong> in certain varieties its phi-<strong>features</strong> surface on <strong>the</strong> accusative<br />

clitic, so that los appears in place <strong>of</strong> lo. If this is <strong>the</strong> right view <strong>of</strong> things, <strong>the</strong><br />

phi-<strong>features</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> surface form los are uninterpreted, since los remains singular<br />

for all interpretive purposes. Under <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r assumption that an argument's interpretable<br />

phi-<strong>features</strong> are not deleted or contradicted by o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dative are simply uninterpretable on <strong>the</strong> accusative.<br />

(24) El libro, a ellos, ¿quién se los prestó?<br />

<strong>the</strong> book, to <strong>the</strong>m, who SE 3PL.ACC lent.3SG<br />

The book, who lent it (3SGM.ACC lo) to <strong>the</strong>m (3PL.DAT les).<br />

(Spanish, Bonet 1995: 634)<br />

All <strong>the</strong>se examples belong to <strong>the</strong> broad domain <strong>of</strong> phi-agreement (Moravcik<br />

1978, Barlow 1988, Wechsler <strong>and</strong> Zlatić 2000, Corbett 2003). It is <strong>the</strong> crosscoding<br />

<strong>of</strong> an argument's phi-<strong>features</strong> on ano<strong>the</strong>r element, (25):<br />

(25) <strong>Phi</strong>-agreement (general): <strong>the</strong> structure, form, or position <strong>of</strong> α that obtains<br />

in virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong> <strong>of</strong> an argument β.<br />

Under (25) fall cross-codings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same abstract character as subject-verb<br />

agreement, but very different in appearance. In canonical subject-verb agreement,<br />

<strong>the</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject are cross-coded outside <strong>the</strong> subject on an agreement<br />

target like T+V, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re <strong>the</strong>y surface through morphology dedicated to expressing<br />

phi-<strong>features</strong>. In <strong>the</strong> repair paradigm (1)/(2), <strong>the</strong> person <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> direct object determines<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> indirect object is a dative clitic or a strong pronoun in a PP<br />

headed by à. The expression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> indirect object thus cross-codes <strong>the</strong> person <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> direct object. This differs from more canonical agreement because <strong>the</strong> direct<br />

object's phi-<strong>features</strong> do not control morphology dedicated to phi-<strong>features</strong>, but it is<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less agreement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form, structure <strong>and</strong>/or position <strong>of</strong> an element (<strong>the</strong><br />

indirect object) with <strong>the</strong> person <strong>of</strong> an argument (<strong>the</strong> direct object). Naturally, <strong>the</strong><br />

underlying mechanism might pass through o<strong>the</strong>r elements, say a clausal functional<br />

head (probe) that drives cliticization. These must still refer to <strong>and</strong> thus agree with<br />

<strong>the</strong> person <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> direct object. 4 In phi-agreement <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong> <strong>of</strong> an argument<br />

are cross-referenced somewhere outside it, where <strong>the</strong>y appear not to be interpreted<br />

or interpretable. They are uninterpretable occurrences <strong>of</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong>.<br />

4 The mechanism that does so in chapter 5 will be phi-feature relativized locality.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!