26.11.2012 Views

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

d. There were shown (*her) to be five <strong>and</strong> seven among <strong>the</strong> primes.<br />

The oddity <strong>of</strong> phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case would vanish if <strong>the</strong>y belonged to PF.<br />

There uninterpretability is a consequence <strong>of</strong> modular architecture. Marantz (2000)<br />

proposes to eliminate phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case from syntax, <strong>and</strong> implements <strong>the</strong>m<br />

in a post-syntactic realizational morphology (cf. Bobaljik 2008, Kratzer 2009). To<br />

this move accrues <strong>the</strong> commitment to enrich realizational morphology with certain<br />

core properties <strong>of</strong> syntax. Among <strong>the</strong>m are those seen in (28): dependencies across<br />

phrase-structurally unbounded domains, sensitive to c-comm<strong>and</strong> among noncontinguous<br />

constituents, <strong>and</strong> syntax-like locality conditions.<br />

These properties are among <strong>the</strong> touchstones that place phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case<br />

in syntax, for <strong>the</strong>y characterize also (A-)movement that is sometimes visible to interpretation.<br />

They are not <strong>the</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> realizational morphology, as will be<br />

seen in chapter 2 through morphological phi-phenomena like that in (24). The postulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a morphology component with <strong>the</strong> necessary syntax-like character<br />

would lift powerful explanatory constraints. It is to be countenanced only if it has<br />

a powerful explanatory recompense. The correct prediction <strong>of</strong> syntactic <strong>and</strong> interpretive<br />

inertness for all phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case might suffice, if <strong>the</strong>y <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

apparently uninterpretable phi-<strong>features</strong> can <strong>the</strong>reby be eliminated from syntax, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> tension <strong>the</strong>y bring to <strong>the</strong> Minimalist Program resolved. 6<br />

However, an extra-syntactic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case is belied by<br />

cases where <strong>the</strong>y do have consequences for syntax <strong>and</strong> interpretation, despite <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

uninterpretability. Chapters 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 develop <strong>the</strong> argument. It comes from interactions<br />

between two DPs according to each o<strong>the</strong>r's person <strong>features</strong>, first between <strong>the</strong><br />

transitive subject <strong>and</strong> object in Ojibwa, Mapudungun, <strong>and</strong> Arizona Tewa, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

from <strong>the</strong> Person Case Constraint <strong>of</strong> (1)/(2) in French. Such 'person hierarchy' interactions<br />

involve phi-agreement in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> (25): <strong>the</strong> form or position <strong>of</strong> an<br />

element – agreement prefix, case-marking, clitic/strong form – depends on phi<strong>features</strong><br />

outside itself <strong>and</strong> uninterpretable on it. Yet <strong>the</strong>re turn out to be effects on<br />

syntax <strong>and</strong> interpretation, <strong>of</strong>ten in minimal contrast with superficially similar phenomena<br />

in morphology. Thus phi-<strong>features</strong> are among syntactic primitives <strong>and</strong><br />

some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir dependencies are formed <strong>the</strong>re. Chapter 6 examines <strong>the</strong> potential interpretive<br />

bases <strong>of</strong> person hierarchy interactions <strong>and</strong> argues <strong>the</strong>y are as uninterpretable<br />

as <strong>the</strong> phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case requirements seen above. 7<br />

6 Marantz's (2000) proposal is made principally on grounds o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> interpretive inertness<br />

<strong>of</strong> phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case, although it follows, <strong>and</strong> is picked up on by work such as Bobaljik<br />

(2008), Kratzer (2009). These grounds are ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> apparent divorce <strong>of</strong> A-movement <strong>and</strong> subject<br />

licensing from phi-agreement <strong>and</strong> Case (Sigurðsson 1991, 2002, Freidin <strong>and</strong> Sprouse 1991,<br />

Schütze 1993, 1997, Frampton <strong>and</strong> Gutmann 1999, Chomsky 2000a, Harley 1995), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> character<br />

<strong>of</strong> 'dependent' Case that appears not to fit <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ile <strong>of</strong> syntactic dependencies (see section<br />

5.5). Marantz's distinctively nonsyntactic morphology is not to be identified with <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

that regular syntactic computation continues after <strong>the</strong> spell-out to LF, before or after Vocabulary<br />

Insertion (Sauerl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Elbourne 2002; Embick <strong>and</strong> Noyer 2001, 2007).<br />

7 Recent work already suggests that phi-Agree may matter for <strong>the</strong> syntactic licensing <strong>of</strong> sig/setype<br />

anaphora, in contrast to <strong>the</strong> interpretive licensing needed in (19), (20) (Reul<strong>and</strong> 2006,<br />

23

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!