26.11.2012 Views

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

Phi-features and the Modular Architecture of - UMR 7023 - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

251<br />

to Agree by locality, if it were embedded within on <strong>and</strong> projected over by its 3SG<br />

phi-set. This seems to allow more latitude for <strong>the</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> pronouns like a<br />

gente in (384), with projection <strong>of</strong> one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir two phi-sets, perhaps <strong>of</strong><br />

both with resolution. The matter also depends on <strong>the</strong> proper treatment <strong>of</strong> local<br />

phrasal reflexives, for which on is 1PL, <strong>and</strong> which might belong to syntax. 191<br />

1PL on <strong>and</strong> similar pronouns indicate that syntactic phi-specifications may be<br />

autonomous <strong>of</strong> interpretive ones. Perhaps interpretive phi-specifications are also<br />

autonomous <strong>of</strong> syntactic ones, but that has not been determined, since on might be<br />

1PL in syntax. This verdict for <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>of</strong> syntax from interpretation is tentative,<br />

since one can imagine reasonable alternatives. 1PL on might have some interpretable<br />

phi-set that conflicts with those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronouns <strong>and</strong> agreement to<br />

which it is linked, in such a way that <strong>the</strong> conflict is resolved to 3SG for some elements<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1PL for o<strong>the</strong>rs, ei<strong>the</strong>r at realization, or in interpretation (through Maximize<br />

Presuppositions (398)). A broader look at similar mismatches suggests this is<br />

not so, for <strong>the</strong>y do not uniformly involve resolution to unmarked values, nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong><br />

number <strong>and</strong> gender (section 6.2), nor <strong>of</strong> person (e.g. Ainu 1PL inclusive for 2SG;<br />

see Corbett 2000: chapter 7, Cysouw 2005). It seems ra<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong> syntactic phi<strong>features</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> an argument may be acquired from <strong>the</strong> evidence supplied by <strong>the</strong> morphology<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> agreement or pronouns or (perhaps) <strong>of</strong> itself.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> 1PL on from Latin 3SG homō 'man', this evidence is <strong>the</strong> synchronic<br />

residue <strong>of</strong> phi-<strong>features</strong> that at an earlier stage were interpretable. The next<br />

section draws a parallel conclusion for [+person] phi-specifications. 192<br />

191 Cf. Wechsler <strong>and</strong> Zlatic's (2003) result that <strong>the</strong>y need ra<strong>the</strong>r than may respect grammatical<br />

gender, discussed in section 6.2.<br />

192 The number <strong>of</strong> on also suggests an uninterpretable SG value. 1PL <strong>and</strong> quasi-universal on necessarily<br />

include more than one entity. However, <strong>the</strong>y may control plural or singular participles<br />

<strong>and</strong> predicate adjectives agreement in (i), reminiscent <strong>of</strong> The committeei hasi/ % havei made<br />

itsi/<strong>the</strong>ir choice (Sauerl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Elbourne 2002), or Someonei said % hei/ % <strong>the</strong>yi saw her (Sauerl<strong>and</strong><br />

2008). However on can have singular adjectives in (i), (ii) with all or with be similar/equal,<br />

where plural agreement is required for committee <strong>and</strong> someone (cf. Winter 2002: 500 note 6,<br />

Kayne 2007: note 5) (so Grevisse <strong>and</strong> Goose 2008: §438b; many speakers do <strong>the</strong>n require plural,<br />

cf. (ii)). Yet participle <strong>and</strong> predicate adjective number/gender agreement in French is ordinarily<br />

semantic ra<strong>the</strong>r than syntactic, e.g. singular for 2PL as 2SG polite <strong>and</strong> 1PL for 1SG authorial<br />

(Wechsler 2004, Corbett 2000; Grevisse <strong>and</strong> Goosse 2008: §438a).<br />

Similar issues may arise for plural predicate adjective agreement with quasi-universal se/si, optional<br />

in French, obligatory in Italian, impossible in Spanish (Mendikoetxea 2008: 296), as well<br />

as 1PL a gente in (384), agreeing optionally for plural in BPP' <strong>and</strong> not at all in BPP. In a syntactic<br />

solution, D'Aless<strong>and</strong>ro (2004) proposes a syntactic PL phi-specification dedicated to concord<br />

for Italian si, cf. <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> Wechsler <strong>and</strong> Zlatić in section 6.2. However, <strong>the</strong>re are diverse types<br />

<strong>of</strong> interpretive plurality to be considered (Corbett 2000; Kratzer 2009, Sauerl<strong>and</strong> 2008, Heim<br />

2008, Harbour 2008, Rullmann 2004, Chierchia 1998, forthc). Particularly relevant may be<br />

1 st /2 nd vs. 3 rd splits for number agreement, for object clitics in Romance (optional vs. obligatory<br />

in Italian, Belletti 2005: 2.2, impossible vs. optional in Catalan, Muxí 1996), <strong>and</strong> for subject-verb<br />

agreement (obligatory vs. impossible across Basque dialects, Rezac 2006: 1.2.2.3).<br />

(i) Oni est (tousi) égal/égaux (à nosi/sesi rois). (on1PL with 1PL nos, on∀ with ses)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!