10.04.2013 Views

An introductory text-book of logic - Mellone, Sydney - Rare Books at ...

An introductory text-book of logic - Mellone, Sydney - Rare Books at ...

An introductory text-book of logic - Mellone, Sydney - Rare Books at ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE GENERAL NATURE OF INDUCTION. 249<br />

ing, which is a fairly simple example, is given by De<br />

Morgan :<br />

&quot;<br />

Observe the pro<strong>of</strong> th<strong>at</strong> the square <strong>of</strong> any number is<br />

equal to as many consecutive odd numbers, beginning<br />

with unity, as there are units<br />

6x6=1 + 3 + 5 + 7 + 9 + 11.<br />

in th<strong>at</strong> number : thus<br />

Take any number, ,<br />

and write down n X n dots in rank and file, so th<strong>at</strong> a dot<br />

represents a unit. To enlarge this figure into (+ i) X<br />

(ti + i ) dots, we must place n more dots <strong>at</strong> each <strong>of</strong> two<br />

adjacent sides, and one more <strong>at</strong> the corner. So th<strong>at</strong> the<br />

square <strong>of</strong> n is changed into the square <strong>of</strong> (+i) by<br />

adding 2/2+1, which is the (+i)th odd number.<br />

(Thus 100 Xi oo is turned into 101 X 101 by adding<br />

the joist odd number, or 201). If then the alleged<br />

theorem be true <strong>of</strong> n X it is therefore true <strong>of</strong> , (+ i) X<br />

(+ But it is true <strong>of</strong> the first<br />

i). number, for i x i = i<br />

;<br />

therefore it is true <strong>of</strong> the second i.e., 2x2 1 + 3; and<br />

and so on.&quot;<br />

therefore <strong>of</strong> the third i.e., 3X3 = 1 + 3 + 5;<br />

Here we have a series <strong>of</strong> terms (i, 2, 3, &c.) in which<br />

we know the rel<strong>at</strong>ion between every pair <strong>of</strong> consecutive<br />

terms. We wish to establish a fact about every term in<br />

it. We suppose th<strong>at</strong> the fact holds <strong>of</strong> any one term,<br />

which we therefore denote by n ; and prove th<strong>at</strong> it holds<br />

<strong>of</strong> the next term, which is +i. We then find by<br />

observ<strong>at</strong>ion th<strong>at</strong> it holds <strong>of</strong> the first term, i ; therefore<br />

it must hold <strong>of</strong> the second, 2 ;<br />

sality <strong>of</strong> the result depends<br />

and so on. The univer<br />

on the fact th<strong>at</strong> the essential<br />

rel<strong>at</strong>ion (which is simply a numerical one) between any<br />

pair <strong>of</strong> consecutive terms is known, as , n + 1 ; and the<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> depends on this alone.<br />

On the other hand, where this pro<strong>of</strong> from the essential<br />

conditions cannot be obtained, we may verify a theorem<br />

in case after case, without being sure th<strong>at</strong> it holds<br />

universally. This is a case <strong>of</strong><br />

&quot;<br />

incomplete induction

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!