10.04.2013 Views

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

norm, so Woodrow Wilson’s liberal internationalism was an overt rejection of the<br />

imperial power struggles and secret diplomacy that had led to the First World War.<br />

Wight defines revolutionists (also sometimes styled ‘Kantians’) as:<br />

those who believe so passionately in the moral unity of the society of states or<br />

international society, that they identify themselves with it, and therefore they<br />

both claim to speak in the name of this unity, and experience an overriding<br />

obligation to give effect to it, as the first aim of their international policies; they<br />

are cosmopolitan rather than internationalist, and their international theory and<br />

policy has a missionary character. 34<br />

In his analysis of Wight, Hedley Bull 35 draws attention to three distinct groups included<br />

in Wight’s characterisation: the religious revolutionists of the Sixteenth and<br />

Seventeenth Centuries (both protestant reformers, and Catholic anti-reformers); the<br />

French revolutionists of the 18 th Century and the respondent ‘international legitimism’<br />

represented in the Congress of Vienna; and the totalitarian revolutionists of the<br />

Twentieth Century, together with their opposites, the counter revolutionists exemplified<br />

by Dullesian anti-communism. Further discussion of Wight will be left until the next<br />

section, and for now we will remain with the more traditional understanding of<br />

liberalism.<br />

If we accept Hobbes, albeit with more than a backward glance to Thucydides, as the<br />

father of modern realism, then for liberalism the analogous place is occupied by John<br />

Locke. Even here, of course, there must be acknowledgment of earlier influences.<br />

Indeed, Barker 36 dubs St Thomas Aquinas ‘the first whig.’ For Aquinas draws a<br />

distinction between three aspects of authority: its principium, ordained by God; its<br />

modus or ‘constitutional form’, determined by the people; and its exercitum, conferred<br />

by – and hence also, when necessary, to be withdrawn by – the people. This line of<br />

thought, and his development particularly of the third aspect – that it is the community<br />

that institutes government and therefore the community may restrain or revoke its<br />

authority – was clearly influential on Locke. The principle that a government owes its<br />

position to the people (‘of all the people, by all the people, for all the people,’ as<br />

Theodore Parker and then, more famously, Abraham Lincoln were later to have it) 37 is<br />

pervasive throughout Locke’s political philosophy and the liberal tradition that ensued,<br />

13

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!