10.04.2013 Views

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

CRANFIELD UNIVERSITY DAREN BOWYER JUST WAR DOCTRINE

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

aversion of Western democracies to fighting ‘symmetric’ wars; the extreme costs – in<br />

money and lives – of a major conflict between broadly equally matched powers had<br />

been all too fully demonstrated by the First World War. The driving force has been to<br />

seek war on terms that minimise risk and cost. This has had particular impact both on<br />

the occasion and conduct of interventions and has led to a reliance on technology,<br />

through which has been sought a significantly advantageous asymmetry.<br />

Risk aversion can limit willingness to intervene or restrict intervention to non-military<br />

and often non-decisive means; it can promote a perception of selective intervention that<br />

undermines claims to moral universality; it can lead to conduct that transfers risk to the<br />

population at large – often those whose ‘rescue’ is providing the jus ad bellum for the<br />

intervention in the first place; and it can result in an inadequate commitment of<br />

manpower that in turn impacts on the conduct of operations.<br />

The desire to minimise both cost and the risk of casualties to ones own side, is an<br />

entirely natural, laudable and morally sound one. However, just war limits this with a<br />

requirement that the risk transferred to non-combatants be proportionate to the military<br />

objective sought (the so-called doctrine of double effect). In humanitarian intervention<br />

operations, when rescue of the civilian populations, or a section of it, is the basis of the<br />

jus ad bellum a different mindset is required, more akin to that of the policeman than<br />

that of the conventional warrior. Moreover, the concept of ‘enemy non-combatant’, that<br />

allows us to avail ourselves of the doctrine of double effect is of dubious if any value in<br />

many contemporary conflicts; not just in interventions and peacekeeping but in war<br />

against non-state entities, for example. Yet at the same time, a growth in risk aversion<br />

has led to a tendency in the west to prefer means of warfare, based on technological<br />

superiority, that can limit both proportionality and discrimination.<br />

To this can be added a concern that the drive to reduce risks to our own troops leads to a<br />

reliance on technologies that allow as to lesser or greater degree to remove the soldier<br />

from the battlefield all together. As such he becomes no longer a warrior but rather a<br />

technician. Not only does distance complicate discrimination (despite the claims for the<br />

‘precision’ of much modern weaponry, which can, of course, also hit ‘precisely’ an<br />

inappropriate target) but, most concerning of all, the moral agent, and most effective<br />

311

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!