04.07.2013 Views

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

126<br />

1. Intransitive preferences<br />

OSCAR HORTA<br />

At fi rst sight, most of us would assume that the “_ is better than _” relation<br />

is transitive. [1] However, theorists such as Larry Temkin (1987; 1996;<br />

1997; forthcoming) and Stuart Rachels (1998; 2001) have argued that this<br />

need not be so. [2] Th ey have presented challenging examples that seriously<br />

question the idea that we need to accept transitivity in axiology. [3] Th eir<br />

argument rests on the fact that we sometimes have intransitive sets of preferences<br />

(or at least many of us <strong>do</strong>). Th is may not happen oft en in everyday<br />

life. [4] But it <strong>do</strong>es happen when we are confronted with cases in which<br />

two diff erent values (or dimensions of one value) confl ict. Most of us have<br />

intuitions (actually, clear intuitions) regarding these cases that are visibly<br />

intransitive.<br />

From this, Rachels and Temkin have concluded that we should give<br />

up the idea that outcomes can be ordered according to transitive sets with<br />

regards to how good they are. Th is is something that strikes most of us as<br />

clearly counterintuitive. Some of us may think that the transitivity of “_ is<br />

better than _” is part of the defi nition of “better”. Others may think that<br />

this is not so, but claim that whatever intuitions we may have regarding<br />

which outcomes are better, they cannot outweigh the strong intuition that<br />

the mentioned relations need to be transitive.<br />

Some may think this is not a very relevant issue, and that this is just a<br />

theoretical problem. However, this is far from being so. First, it is something<br />

that can be particularly relevant when it comes to designing general<br />

policies. Second, it poses a formidable problem for value theory as such.<br />

1 For the sake of simplicity, in this paper I will focus on what is better, rather than on preferences.<br />

At some points, I may say that we prefer one outcome to another one, but I will usually say that<br />

we have certain intuitions concerning which outcomes are better. Th is may imply the assumption<br />

of a realist position regarding personal value. However, the claims made in this paper may<br />

also be accepted by those who disagree with this view.<br />

2 On this see also, among others, Norcross (1999); Aldred (2002); Chan (2003); Qizilbash (2005);<br />

Dorsey (2009).<br />

3 Th ese problems, which aff ect the very core of practical reason, are addressed in much detail in<br />

Temkin (forthcoming).<br />

4 Th ere are, though, some cases in which we <strong>do</strong> have intransitive sets of preferences. Moreover, in<br />

some cases we would say it is not particularly odd to have such sets of preferences. We may, for<br />

instance, prefer to buy a new cheap computer rather than going on working with our old one.<br />

But we may also prefer to buy a not so cheap but better computer rather than the cheap one. And<br />

then, we may think that the more expensive computer is not worth its money, insofar as our old<br />

one still works. It would defi nitely be better for someone with this set of preferences to get rid of<br />

at least one of them. Yet we would not say that she would be crazy or obtuse for having them.<br />

<strong>Diacritica</strong> <strong>25</strong>-2_<strong>Filosofia</strong>.<strong>indb</strong> 126 05-01-2012 09:38:<strong>25</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!