04.07.2013 Views

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

TIME PREFERENCE AND INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE<br />

bers of future generations. Individuals would have the duty to sacrifi ce their<br />

own consumption in the present to transmit their income and resources<br />

to the next generation, in the hypothesis that well-being is synonymous of<br />

accumulation of capital (wealth, but also natural resources, cultural patrimony,<br />

etc.).<br />

More fundamentally, a positive social discount rate is denounced by<br />

Liberal egalitarians because of its incompatibility with the principle of equal<br />

liberty for all, especially for future generations. According to the Maximin<br />

principle, it could be legitimate to accord a social priority to current generations<br />

because future one will be richer. But it appears unjust to accord a<br />

social priority to individuals only because of their position in time:<br />

In the case of society, pure time preference is unjust: it means (in the more<br />

common distance when the future is discounted) that the living take advantage<br />

of their position in time to favour their own interests. “(...) [W]e are not<br />

allowed to treat generations diff erently solely on the grounds that they are earlier<br />

or later in time” (Rawls, 1999: 260).<br />

Liberal-egalitarian philosophers focused on Intergenerational justice<br />

claim for temporal neutrality or impartiality to underline our duty to take<br />

equally into account all individuals, whatever their position in time. And<br />

as economists, such a moral claim results from a specifi c perception of<br />

individual behaviour in time. But according to them, individuals <strong>do</strong> not<br />

develop subjective time preference. In Th eory of Justice, Rawls assumed that<br />

principles of justice are determined by individual participants in a pure<br />

procedure, named original contract. [6] Th ese participants are under a veil of<br />

ignorance: they <strong>do</strong> not know their social situation, their standard of living<br />

or their own conception of good life. Th ey are then supposed to defi ne principles<br />

of justice not on the ground of their particular position, but on general<br />

considerations (Idem, 118-123). Principles of justice are then justifi ed<br />

by the choices of participants under a veil of ignorance. And his intuitions<br />

about Intergenerational justice are also justifi ed on the ground of refl ections<br />

about individual behaviour in time under a veil of ignorance.<br />

As economists, he observes that individuals in general could give their<br />

preference to a present satisfaction and could develop a time preference.<br />

But such a preference can be explained only by objective factors. He considers<br />

then that individuals <strong>do</strong> not develop pure or subjective time prefer-<br />

6 Two principles of justice have been emphasized. Th e fi rst principle is equal liberty for all. Th e<br />

second principle is about social and economic inequalities: they are fair only whether they<br />

result from equal opportunity for all and they maximise the situation of the least advantaged<br />

(Rawls, 1999).<br />

<strong>Diacritica</strong> <strong>25</strong>-2_<strong>Filosofia</strong>.<strong>indb</strong> 55 05-01-2012 09:38:20<br />

55

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!