04.07.2013 Views

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

132<br />

5. Possible global solutions to spectrum cases<br />

OSCAR HORTA<br />

Th e way in which the problem at stake here can be approached will vary<br />

signifi cantly depending of which one of the metho<strong>do</strong>logical perspectives<br />

presented above we assume. In this section I will examine what solutions<br />

may be given to this problem according to each of these perspectives.<br />

(i) Considering Only Particular Preferences towards Outcomes. At fi rst<br />

sight, an obvious candidate to be the most preferable option is A 1 . Th e<br />

sum of the local intuitions we have when we compare consecutive pairs<br />

of alternatives in the spectrum would drive us to conclude this. However,<br />

if we reject all the constraints any principle may impose, we <strong>do</strong> not need<br />

to accept this. We no longer need to add our local intuitions. We just need<br />

to take into account the intuitions we may have towards diff erent pairs of<br />

outcomes. According to this approach, in each evaluation of a certain pair<br />

of outcomes we are not constrained by what principles may tell us about<br />

which one is preferable. Given this, we may reject A 1 if we have the intuition<br />

that another option is better than it. Th ere are several possible solutions<br />

alternative to this one that those who are just concerned with intuitions<br />

towards outcomes can assume.<br />

Suppose we have an intransitive set of intuitions regarding the betterness<br />

of diff erent outcomes: A>B>C>A. It may happen that when we look<br />

closely at the problem, we discover that the degree to which we think one<br />

alternative is better than another one may vary when we consider diff erent<br />

pairs of alternatives. So we may think A is slightly better than B and B<br />

slightly better than C, but C strongly better than A. Th is set could then be<br />

represented as follows: A> 1 B> 1 C> 10 A. In light of this, we could decide to<br />

choose C as the strongest option. And we may try to <strong>do</strong> the same in the<br />

spectrum case we are considering here. Accordingly, we might think that<br />

the strongest preference would be the one we have for A n over A 1 , and conclude,<br />

due to it, that A n is the best option.<br />

Th is solution, however, would be problematic. A n-1 seems to be better<br />

than A n , and in fact it also seems to be intuitively much better than A 1 . But<br />

then, where should we stop? A n-2 seems to be even better. In light of this<br />

problem, we may simply assume that we just need to take into account our<br />

direct intuitions regarding each of the available options over the next one in<br />

the spectrum. But this leaves us with no candidate for global betterness.<br />

Th ere is a way, however, in which we may try to look for a solution for<br />

this problem. In spectrum cases such as the ones we have seen here, A n<br />

<strong>Diacritica</strong> <strong>25</strong>-2_<strong>Filosofia</strong>.<strong>indb</strong> 132 05-01-2012 09:38:<strong>25</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!