04.07.2013 Views

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

Diacritica 25-2_Filosofia.indb - cehum - Universidade do Minho

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

148<br />

RUI SILVA<br />

emotions and virtue; virtues are not only dispositions to action, but also<br />

to moderate our emotions or to feel in a certain way. From an Aristotelian<br />

standpoint, “having the right emotions is necessary for being a good person”<br />

(Stocker, 1996: 174).<br />

Th e important connections between value and emotions are another<br />

sign of the ethical importance of emotions. In fact, many emotions contain<br />

an evaluation of their object (anger, love, for instance), and the lack<br />

of emotions may lead to a devaluation of other beings (as the existence of<br />

psychopaths demonstrates). As Stocker (1996: 177) put it, correct emotions<br />

lead to correct evaluations and incorrect emotions make it diffi cult to make<br />

correct evaluations. Th e relevance of emotions for virtue ethics can be also<br />

illustrated by Hume’s defence of sympathy and Schopenhauer’s defence of<br />

compassion as the basis of morality.<br />

Today, it is no longer a speculation to claim that emotions play a fundamental<br />

role in our decision-making processes; this point is widely acknowledged<br />

by neuroscientists. So, when we say that practical reason requires a<br />

certain form of upbringing or personal development, we should bear in<br />

mind the Aristotelian idea that such a process must involve the education<br />

or training of emotions. Th e humanist idea of Bildung is, once more, very<br />

useful in this context, especially if we consider Schillers’ thesis that Bildung<br />

requires not only philosophical culture, but also aesthetic education. Bildung<br />

was considered an intellectual and aff ective process.<br />

3. It seems legitimate to consider communitarianism as a natural translation<br />

of virtue ethics into the <strong>do</strong>main of political philosophy; the work<br />

of MacIntyre provides a good illustration of the similarities between both<br />

movements. In order to clarify this point, it is convenient to sketch out a<br />

brief characterization of communitarianism. It is usual to defi ne communitarianism<br />

in contrast with liberalism, and this contrast can be made at<br />

diff erent levels:<br />

– at the ethical level, there is a defence of particularism and of the thesis<br />

that the ends and values involved in moral reasoning have a social origin;<br />

– at the anthropological level, communitarian authors criticize individualistic<br />

and atomistic conceptions of the self;<br />

– at the political level, it is argued that the goods favoured by a community<br />

should play an important role in political decisions;<br />

– fi nally, communitarians denounce liberalism’s internal tensions or<br />

“pragmatic contradiction”: far from being neutral regarding the diff erent<br />

conceptions of the good, liberalism belongs to a particular tradition.<br />

<strong>Diacritica</strong> <strong>25</strong>-2_<strong>Filosofia</strong>.<strong>indb</strong> 148 05-01-2012 09:38:27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!