13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE DEFENCE OF PNC 125But we may note that apparently Priest ignores these qualificati<strong>on</strong>s, anddoes so deliberately, because his primary aim here is to argue that PNC isnot obviously true, and that, if it is true at all, this has to be shown. If thisis indeed Priest’s primary aim, it is <strong>on</strong>e which <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> wholly shares. Wewill see (in this chapter and Chapter 6) that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> goes to great lengthto defend PNC. He does not at all think that PNC is obviously true.But there may also be a deeper point behind the need to add suchqualificati<strong>on</strong>s. If PNC is to be true, it must be understood to say not <strong>on</strong>lythat a property (e.g. redness or moti<strong>on</strong>) cannot be both true of and not trueof a single thing, in a loose sense of ‘a single thing’. For the tomato is asingle thing in spite of the various times of its existence, and it can be bothred and not red; the shirt is a single thing in spite of its various patterns,and it can be both red and not red; the spinning-top is a single thing inspite of its various geometrical parts, and it can be both in moti<strong>on</strong> and notin moti<strong>on</strong>. Rather, if PNC is to be true, it must be understood to say thata property (e.g. redness or moti<strong>on</strong>) cannot be both true of and not true of asingle thing, in a more strict sense of ‘single’ or ‘unitary’ thing. Forexample, if PNC is to be true of the spinning-top, it must be understoodto say that moti<strong>on</strong> cannot at any particular time be both true of and nottrue of the very same aspect or part of the spinning-top, e.g. itscircumference or its axis.So <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>, like Plato, argues that, if we at all want to defend thepropositi<strong>on</strong> that PNC is true of things and of all things, we need toinvestigate with particular care various ways in which things may or maynot be unitary. This point is extremely important. For it suggests that hethinks that, if we at all want to defend that PNC is true of things and of allthings, we need to engage in metaphysics and to ask the questi<strong>on</strong>, ‘What isit for something, anything, to be a being, something that is?’ Indeed, inIV. 2 he argues that to investigate what it is for something, anything, to bea being, is to investigate what it is for something, anything, to be <strong>on</strong>ething. In general this is because metaphysics is centrally c<strong>on</strong>cerned withthe individuati<strong>on</strong> of things, i.e. with the questi<strong>on</strong> of what it is for a thingto be <strong>on</strong>e or many; and to this issue bel<strong>on</strong>gs the examinati<strong>on</strong> of howthings may or may not be unitary. So the investigati<strong>on</strong> into various ways inwhich things may or may not be unitary, which is also necessary in orderto defend PNC, bel<strong>on</strong>gs at the core of metaphysics.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!