13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CRITICISM OF PLATO’S THEORY OF FORMS 319distinctness is necessarily symmetrical. This means that if a thing, x, isdistinct from another thing, y, then it follows that y is likewise distinctfrom x. But certainly it is not true that if a form, F, can exist without thereexisting a changing thing, x, that is F, then a changing thing, x, that is Fcan likewise exist without there existing a form, F. On the c<strong>on</strong>trary, even ifPlato thinks that a form, F, can exist without there existing a changingthing, x, that is F, he also thinks that a changing thing, x, that is F is F<strong>on</strong>ly because there is a form, F, and x is appropriately related to this form—it participates in or <strong>com</strong>munes with this form. So this relati<strong>on</strong>, the relati<strong>on</strong>between changing things and forms, is not necessarily symmetrical, indeedit is necessarily asymmetrical. This shows that we cannot infer from ‘FormF is distinct from changing things’ that ‘Form F can exist without beingtrue of changing things’.So, if we think that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> characterizes Plato’s forms not <strong>on</strong>ly asdistinct from changing things, which is the central target of his criticism,but also as capable of existing without being true of changing things, we mustask how he moves from the former to the latter characterizati<strong>on</strong>. Perhaps hedefends this move in the following way: Plato’s forms are not <strong>on</strong>ly distinctfrom changing things, they are also, and above all, things that are beingssimply in virtue of themselves; but from these two characteristics of theforms, i.e. their being distinct and their being <strong>on</strong>tologically independent, itfollows that they can exist without being true of changing things, and, ingeneral, without changing things existing in relati<strong>on</strong> to them. If this is<str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s reas<strong>on</strong>ing, then it may well be cogent. For it is perhaps plausibleto think that if a thing, x, is a being simply in virtue of itself and not invirtue of its relati<strong>on</strong> to another thing, y; and if, further, x is distinct fromy, then it does indeed follow that x can exist without y existing in relati<strong>on</strong>to x. But it would take us too far to c<strong>on</strong>sider this further.These, then, are three ways in which <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> characterizes Plato’sessences and forms as separate:(1) separate in the sense of being <strong>on</strong>tologically independent beings, i.e.things that are beings simply in virtue of themselves;(2) separate in the sense of being distinct from changing things; and(3) separate in the sense of being capable of existing without being true ofchanging things.We have also c<strong>on</strong>sidered how these three types of separati<strong>on</strong> are related toeach other.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> argues against distinctness, and this is the main target of hiscriticism of Plato’s theory of essence—the theory of forms. He c<strong>on</strong>cludes

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!