13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CRITICISM OF PLATO’S THEORY OF FORMS 317Plato’s forms—which is the main target of his criticism. So the target ofthe criticism is the view that changing things and forms are things that aredistinct from <strong>on</strong>e another. The noti<strong>on</strong> of two things being distinct from<strong>on</strong>e another is familiar especially when applied to things in space. For suchthings are evidently distinct from <strong>on</strong>e another if they occupy different andn<strong>on</strong>-overlapping places. But what in general is it for two things to bedistinct from <strong>on</strong>e another? This questi<strong>on</strong> is pressing; for evidently Plato’sforms, if they are in general distinct from changing things, do not as suchoccupy a place in space. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> does not provide a general account ofwhat it is for two things to be distinct from <strong>on</strong>e another. But he appears tohave in mind the following: two things are distinct from <strong>on</strong>e another if, and<strong>on</strong>ly if:(1) they are not identical; and(2) they are not overlapping, i.e. they do not share any part.We saw earlier that separati<strong>on</strong> in the sense of <strong>on</strong>tological independencedoes not entail separati<strong>on</strong> in the sense of distinctness; and <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> doesnot think that there is such an entailment (see Chapter 7§4). So when hecharacterizes Plato’s essences and forms as separate things in the sense ofthings that are distinct from changing things, he is not simply drawing ac<strong>on</strong>sequence from the characterizati<strong>on</strong> of them as separate in the sense of<strong>on</strong>tologically independent things, i.e. things that are beings simply invirtue of themselves. In particular, the characterizati<strong>on</strong> of Plato’s essences as<strong>on</strong>tologically independent beings is simply part of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s observati<strong>on</strong>that the forms are, in Plato’s view, the primary beings (hai ousiai). But theview that essences are distinct from changing things, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinks, reliesrather <strong>on</strong> a <strong>com</strong>plex argument, which is based <strong>on</strong> the claim that, whileessences are changeless, changing things are changing (see §3 of thischapter).So <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> characterizes Plato’s essences and forms as separate in twoways or senses:(1) they are <strong>on</strong>tologically independent beings, i.e. they are beings, thingsthat are, simply in virtue of themselves; and(2) they are distinct from changing things.Apparently, he also characterizes Plato’s essences as separate in a thirdsense, i.e. as (3) capable of existing even if they are not true of changingthings, i.e. even if they are not, as is sometimes said today,‘instantiated in’changing things. In other words, he apparently thinks that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!