13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

72 ARISTOTLE’S METHOD IN METAPHYSICSAn aporia provides directi<strong>on</strong> and aim to a search because of its logicaland dilemmatic structure, i.e. its being a questi<strong>on</strong> with two apparentlyopposite and c<strong>on</strong>flicting sides, with good reas<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> both sides. C<strong>on</strong>sider,for example, the central questi<strong>on</strong> of metaphysics, ‘What is being?’ Asstated, it is not yet an aporia, although it may be closely associated withaporiai; for it is not structured as an aporia, i.e. as a questi<strong>on</strong> that has twosides. At the same time, and apparently because it is not yet structured asan aporia, this questi<strong>on</strong> does not indicate any directi<strong>on</strong>s for searching, andit may even appear to be without aim. But now let us suppose that thisquesti<strong>on</strong>, ‘What is being?’, is associated with a particular aporia about thenature of being, such as: ‘Is being primarily something particular orsomething general?’ (see the last aporia, number 15, in book III). Supposealso that we have some initial grasp of why both answers to this questi<strong>on</strong>appear genuinely attractive. Then our search is provided with directi<strong>on</strong> andaim. For we know what in general we have to do to answer a dilemma:either defend the <strong>on</strong>e side; or the other side; or argue that the two sides canafter all be rec<strong>on</strong>ciled. So we immediately have available certain paths forsearching.On the other hand, it is also worth pointing out that these paths forsearching may not be as clearly and distinctly marked out as we might think.For an important part of the search for an answer to an aporia will involvegiving an adequate account of the central c<strong>on</strong>cepts in the aporia; forexample, the c<strong>on</strong>cepts of particulars and universals. But in giving such anaccount it may emerge that different answers to the aporia are called for,depending <strong>on</strong> how its central c<strong>on</strong>cepts are understood. So the paths forsearching generated by an aporia may depend <strong>on</strong> how the central c<strong>on</strong>ceptsin the aporia are understood.But it is also important not to misunderstand this point. For it does notmean that we must first clarify the c<strong>on</strong>cepts and engage in what today issometimes called c<strong>on</strong>ceptual analysis, before we may try to answer theaporia. On the c<strong>on</strong>trary, the c<strong>on</strong>ceptual inquiry is itself an integral part ofthe attempt to answer the aporia. Indeed, it is the endeavour to answer theaporia that generates the need for, and gives directi<strong>on</strong> to, the c<strong>on</strong>ceptualinquiry. Without aporiai, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual inquiries are themselves aimless—andperhaps pointless.A particular aporia evidently provides us with a way of telling (acriteri<strong>on</strong>) when a search has been successfully <strong>com</strong>pleted, that is, when theaporia has been adequately answered. So an aporia c<strong>on</strong>tributes not <strong>on</strong>ly ameans of searching, but also a criteri<strong>on</strong> of finding. However, this aporiabasedcriteri<strong>on</strong> of finding is neither infallible nor definitive. It is notinfallible, since there is nothing in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s general c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of an

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!