13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

326 CRITICISM OF PLATO’S THEORY OF FORMSit means that it is not satisfactory to paint the following, simplistic, pictureof the debate between Plato and <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> about essence: Plato,extravagantly and unnecessarily, made essences separate and distinct fromsense-perceptible and, in general, changing things; <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> restoredessences to where they obviously bel<strong>on</strong>g, namely, in the sense-perceptibleand, in general, the changing things. There is a particular reas<strong>on</strong> why thispicture is simplistic. For to say simply that, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>, essencesare in the sense-perceptible things, although it is true as far as it goes, is tooverlook that there is a fundamental problem in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>, and <strong>on</strong>e that hehimself raises and sets out to answer: how is the essence of a changingthing related to that thing itself and in particular to the ultimate subject ofpredicati<strong>on</strong>? As we saw at length earlier (in Chapter 7, especially §§5v–viii), it is above all this problem that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> raises and sets out to answerin the central books of the <strong>Metaphysics</strong>, and especially book VII.6<str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s criticism, based <strong>on</strong> Plato’s theory ofessence: the third-man argumentBut <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> also argues that Plato’s theory of essences as separate anddistinct forms leads to absurd c<strong>on</strong>sequences even <strong>on</strong> its own merit andindependently of his, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s, alternative theory of essence. One absurdc<strong>on</strong>sequence, he argues, is that if there is <strong>on</strong>e separate and distinct form of,for example, human beings, i.e. distinct from the changing human beingswith which we are directly familiar from sense percepti<strong>on</strong> and experience,then there will be infinitely many separate and distinct forms of the humanbeing. He labels this attempt to reduce Plato’s theory to absurdity ‘thethird-man’ argument: we start with the human beings with which we arefamiliar from sense percepti<strong>on</strong> and experience (this is the first man); butPlat<strong>on</strong>ists postulate a sec<strong>on</strong>d human being, namely, the separate and distinctform of the human being (this is the sec<strong>on</strong>d man); but this, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>argues, leads to the absurd c<strong>on</strong>sequence that we must postulate a furtherseparate and distinct form of the human being (the third man), and so <strong>on</strong>without end. The moral that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> wants to draw from this criticism isthat we should not postulate a sec<strong>on</strong>d human being, i.e. a human beingthat is separate and distinct from changing <strong>on</strong>es, in the first place.The polemical intent of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s criticism is evident already in thelabel ‘the third man’. For to use this label is to portray Plato’s form of thehuman being as simply another human being: a human being which isentirely like those with which we are familiar from sense percepti<strong>on</strong> andexperience, except that it is changeless and everlasting—as it were in a deep

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!