13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE ULTIMATE EXPLANATIONS OF ALL THINGS 47things, and investigates them in so far as they are extended, etc.<strong>Metaphysics</strong>, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, investigates simply beings, and itinvestigates them simply in so far as they are.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> shares with Plato these fundamental requirements forexplanati<strong>on</strong> (R1–5)—though they disagree fundamentally about whatthings have essences. But in the Posterior Analytics <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> developed atheory of the structure of explanati<strong>on</strong> and explanatory reas<strong>on</strong>ing, based <strong>on</strong>his theory of the structure of deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing, which he developed inthe Prior Analytics. According to this theory, explanatory reas<strong>on</strong>ing, whichhe calls ‘dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>’ (apodeixis), is a kind of deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing(sullogismos). For a piece of deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing to c<strong>on</strong>stitute adem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>, it must be an explanatory deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing (sullogismosepistēm<strong>on</strong>ikos, see Posterior Analytics I. 2, 71 b 17–19). This means that thetruth of the premises in the deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing must not <strong>on</strong>ly entail thatthe c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is true, it must also explain why the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is true. Todo so, the premises must in general be more explanatory than thec<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>. So <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinks that explanatory knowledge (epistēmē) aimsat dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>, i.e. at using deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing to derive explanatoryc<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s from more explanatory premises; and he thinks that there arepremises that are most explanatory and cannot themselves be explainedfurther. These are the premises that state the first and ultimateexplanati<strong>on</strong>s.Finally, there is a basic suppositi<strong>on</strong> in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s (and Plato’s)c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of science, which is so evident to him that he nowhereexpressly states or c<strong>on</strong>siders it (the same is true of Plato). But thissuppositi<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>e that we may disagree with, so it is important to make itexplicit.R6. SCIENTIFIC REALISMIt is things that have explanati<strong>on</strong>s, and explanati<strong>on</strong>s are themselvesthings and features of things. So explanati<strong>on</strong>s are things and features ofthings, not what we think or say about things. Of course, if we knowthings that explain other things, and, if we know that, and how theyexplain other things, then we have explanatory knowledge of things. And<str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinks that such knowledge can be stated in statements. Still,explanati<strong>on</strong>s are things, not our thoughts or statements about things. Aswe would say, he thinks that explanati<strong>on</strong>s are independent of us, ourthought and our language. So he thinks that essences, too, which is whatexplanati<strong>on</strong>s are based in, are independent of us, our thought andlanguage. The same is true of the general kinds to which things bel<strong>on</strong>g,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!