13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE ULTIMATE CAUSE OF CHANGE: GOD 281an object of rati<strong>on</strong>al thought and desire. This is how the ultimate cause ofchange can move the outermost heaven without itself changing or moving.This account of the causati<strong>on</strong> distinctive of the ultimate cause of changeis not easy to <strong>com</strong>prehend, but certainly it serves to dissociate the causati<strong>on</strong>distinctive of the ultimate cause of change from a kind of causati<strong>on</strong> thatdepends <strong>on</strong> interacti<strong>on</strong>, and to associate it instead with the way in whichan intelligent or rati<strong>on</strong>al organism is caused to move when it recognizesthat something is good and worth pursuing. So <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>ceives of thecausal relati<strong>on</strong> between the ultimate cause of change and the outermostheaven in teleological or final terms. For the ultimate cause of change isthe good which is the end (telos) of the thought and desire of theoutermost heaven, and in general of the cosmos that is delimited andunified by this heaven. The ultimate cause of change moves by being anobject of thought and desire, not by interacti<strong>on</strong>. We may sum up by sayingthat the ultimate cause of change is a teleological or final cause, as opposedto an efficient cause that relies <strong>on</strong> interacti<strong>on</strong>.But although <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> clearly rejects the view that the ultimate cause ofchange is an efficient cause that relies <strong>on</strong> interacti<strong>on</strong>, he appears to thinkthat it is an efficient cause in a broader sense. For the ultimate cause ofchange is not simply the object of thought and desire of the cosmos, it is asupremely real thing and it ‘produces’ this thought and desire in thecosmos, i.e. it causes the cosmos to have this thought and desire. If theultimate cause of change had been simply the object of thought and desireof the cosmos, it need not have been different from merely imaginarythings; for they can be just as much objects of thought and desire. Forexample, I may imagine the house that I am planning to build; and thisimaginary house, we may say loosely speaking, may cause me to build it.But obviously what causes me to act here is not a real house at all, but myown thoughts and imaginings which represent a house. By c<strong>on</strong>trast,suppose that I am hungry and that I see an apple hanging from a branch;then this apple, the real thing that I recognize, may produce in me thedesire for it and the thought of how I may reach it. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s ultimatecause of change is like the sec<strong>on</strong>d case, not like the first; and in this sensethe ultimate cause of change functi<strong>on</strong>s not <strong>on</strong>ly as a teleological or finalcause, but also as an efficient cause, ‘a productive cause’ (poiētik<strong>on</strong>), as hecalls it. But it is striking that this efficient cause, the ultimate cause ofchange, does not rely <strong>on</strong> interacti<strong>on</strong> for its causati<strong>on</strong>.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!