13.07.2015 Views

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

Aristotle on Metaphysics(2004) - Bibotu.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

16 ARISTOTLE’S METAPHYSICStwo things, <strong>on</strong>e being true of the other, the former relati<strong>on</strong>, i.e. the relati<strong>on</strong>between a particular (e.g. Socrates) and its essence (e.g. being human) is arelati<strong>on</strong> between a thing and itself.This also helps to clarify what <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> means by the essence (to ti estin,to ti ēn einai). For it shows that he argues that particulars, indeed thechanging particulars with which we are directly familiar from sensepercepti<strong>on</strong> and experience (e.g. Socrates), have an essence, i.e. there issomething that they are simply in virtue of themselves (auta kath’ hauta).This stands in c<strong>on</strong>trast especially with Plato, who argues that <strong>on</strong>ly universalshave an essence, and that particulars depend for their determinati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>their relati<strong>on</strong> to universals. But this fundamental disagreement about whatthings have an essence takes place against the background of a sharedgeneral c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of essence: the essence, E, of a thing, x, is what x issimply in virtue of itself and in virtue of its being the very thing it is, x.Or, less formally: the essence of a thing is what we know when we knowthe answer to the questi<strong>on</strong>, ‘What is this very thing?’5Does <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> assume essentialism in the <strong>Metaphysics</strong>?Let us call ‘essentialism’ the view which says that:(1) there are things that have an essence; and(2) what the essence of a thing is does not depend <strong>on</strong> how we refer to thatthing or in general how we think or speak about it.There is no doubt that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> holds this view. But does he simplyassume essentialism in the <strong>Metaphysics</strong>, or does he defend it? If he simplyassumes essentialism, then this may be a cause of c<strong>on</strong>cern. Indeed, we maythink that there is a particular cause of c<strong>on</strong>cern especially if we areimpressed by Quine’s argument against essentialism (see e.g. Quine 1953).So we may think that there is a basic cause of c<strong>on</strong>cern about <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s<strong>Metaphysics</strong> before we have even started looking at it.Two resp<strong>on</strong>ses are appropriate to this cause of c<strong>on</strong>cern. On the <strong>on</strong>ehand, even if <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> simply assumes essentialism in the <strong>Metaphysics</strong>,Quine’s argument against essentialism ought not to be a cause of c<strong>on</strong>cern.For the c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of essentialism that Quine’s argument is directedagainst is crucially different from <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of essentialism. Onthe other hand, we will see that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Aristotle</str<strong>on</strong>g> does not simply assumeessentialism in the <strong>Metaphysics</strong>—rather he defends this view.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!