06.05.2013 Views

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

LUCRETIUS<br />

was not Epicurus, but his persistent claims to be treading in his master's<br />

footsteps <strong>and</strong> the closeness of many of his arguments to the surviving Greek<br />

text suggests that his main debt was to the philosopher himself. 1 If this conclusion<br />

is correct, then Lucretius must have undertaken a considerable reorganization<br />

of his philosophical material. The problem which he faced was not<br />

simply that of the expositor who must present his argument in the most logical<br />

manner possible. As a poet he needed also to create a feeling of unity <strong>and</strong> to<br />

direct <strong>and</strong> condition the reader's response. To achieve this larger purpose,<br />

Lucretius concentrated on the anti-theological elements in Epicurean thought<br />

<strong>and</strong> put them in the forefront of his poem. The process begins in the opening<br />

prologue. This contains two programmatic passages separated by about seventy<br />

lines which between them summarize the contents of the work. The first (54—<br />

61) mentions the atoms <strong>and</strong> die working of the heavens <strong>and</strong> die second (127—35)<br />

stresses the nature of the soul. Some commentators have thought that these<br />

two passages represent different stages in the composition of the prologue <strong>and</strong><br />

this may be so; but in fact both are necessary to indicate the scope of the poem.<br />

The De rerum natura, as Lucretius presents it, is a work about the soul <strong>and</strong><br />

about the heavens. It is significant that Aristotle traced the origin of belief in the<br />

gods to these same two factors, -ret -irepi yuxr|v <strong>and</strong> TO peiicopa,' die experiences<br />

of die soul' <strong>and</strong> 'celestial phenomena' (fr. 10 Rose). This is die clue to the<br />

structure of Lucretius' poem; after die first two books have laid the necessary<br />

dieoretical foundation, Books 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 deal widi the soul <strong>and</strong> die senses <strong>and</strong><br />

Books 5 <strong>and</strong> 6 widi die heavens <strong>and</strong> the gods. The whole concept of die poem<br />

is determined by its dieological position. Once this is clear, not only the general<br />

outline of die work but also some of its details fall into place. For example<br />

Book 4, after die brilliant satiric passage about die nature of love, ends radier<br />

quietly widi two paragraphs, the first on sterility <strong>and</strong> the second about die<br />

unattractive woman. At first reading they may appear somediing of an anticlimax;<br />

but diere is nothing arbitrary or makeshift about diem. In the first<br />

Lucretius shows that sterility is not caused by die gods <strong>and</strong> diat prayers to<br />

heaven will be of no avail. The second passage is designed to show that improbable<br />

unions are not die work of heaven <strong>and</strong> diat the shafts of Venus have nothing<br />

to do widi die matter. Both are part of the anti-theological argument<br />

of die poem.<br />

This preoccupation with religion may correspond to something deep in<br />

Lucretius' nature. It is possible to argue, as many have done, that the attack<br />

on superstition was die main motivation for the poem. But the critic should<br />

also be aware of the importance of the religious polemic as an organizing device.<br />

It is diis which holds die argument togedier <strong>and</strong> gives it its emotional force.<br />

One may suspect that Lucretius sometimes exaggerated this aspect of Epicurean<br />

1 On Lucretius' sources see Giussani (1896) 1—17.<br />

218<br />

Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!