06.05.2013 Views

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

Kenney_and_Clausen B.M.W.(eds.) - Get a Free Blog

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

APULEIUS<br />

return to Carthage. The few evidences of dating are confined to the 160s, <strong>and</strong><br />

the snatches of civic addresses to Roman officials, references to tenure of the<br />

chief priesthood <strong>and</strong> to honorific statues, <strong>and</strong> the pungent odour of complacent<br />

self-satisfaction reveal him as the province's social lion of that decade. The<br />

passages have a homogeneity in that each is part of a personal exordium<br />

prefacing a speech or lecture, the content being polite philosophy for everyman.<br />

Apuleius makes his public appearances as the African Plutarch, discoursing<br />

now on the life-style of Hippias or Crates, now on the voyages of Pythagoras<br />

or the gymnosophists of India.<br />

II<br />

The extant philosophical works traditionally attributed to Apuleius are De<br />

deo Socratis, De Platone et eius dogmate, De mundo, TTepl fepiiTivefas, <strong>and</strong><br />

Asclepius. The authenticity of the first is generally accepted, though the praefatio<br />

is now assigned to the Florida. Scholars have been divided about the second<br />

<strong>and</strong> third because of their less exuberant style, but this may be explicable not<br />

only by an earlier date but also by the likelihood that the De deo Socratis was<br />

declaimed whereas the other two were written with no epideictic intent for<br />

a reading public. The content <strong>and</strong> attitudes revealed in the works encourage<br />

attribution of them to Apuleius, as does identification of the author by the<br />

manuscripts <strong>and</strong> by Augustine. The TTepl Ipunveicxs (' On interpretation') has<br />

less well authenticated claims, for it appears in a separate manuscript-tradition,<br />

<strong>and</strong> is more jejune in content; it cannot however be dismissed out of h<strong>and</strong> as<br />

non-Apuleian. The Asclepius is a Latin translation by an unknown h<strong>and</strong> of a<br />

lost Greek hermetic work. This brief survey of Apuleius' importance as philosopher<br />

concentrates on the first three of the five treatises.<br />

De deo Socratis ('On Socrates' god') is a thoroughly misleading title, for<br />

Apuleius' primary concern is to preach the existence of demons in general; the<br />

treatise has immense importance in the history of ideas as the most systematic<br />

exposition of the subject from the ancient world. With admirable clarity of<br />

structure the first section surveys the separated worlds of gods (visible stars<br />

<strong>and</strong> invisible members of the Pantheon) <strong>and</strong> of men; the second part describes<br />

the place of demons in the hierarchy of rational beings as intermediaries between<br />

the two. After outlining their role <strong>and</strong> nature, Apuleius assigns them into three<br />

classes. The first are souls within human bodies. The second have quitted<br />

human shape to become Lemures, Lares, Larvae, Manes. The third are wholly<br />

free of bodily connexions, being endowed with special powers <strong>and</strong> allotted<br />

specific duties. Somnus <strong>and</strong> Amor are offered as examples, the second being of<br />

particular interest to the student of the Metamorphoses. The nature of Socrates'<br />

demon forms the final section; Apuleius labels it deus because this is the word<br />

familiar to his readers from Cicero <strong>and</strong> Ovid. The protreptic conclusion<br />

776<br />

Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!