04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

102 Chapter 3<br />

The reasons for thinking that the burden placed on the church may<br />

have been substantial need further discussion. The first reason to think so<br />

is the idea that churches transmit beliefs and moral values through the<br />

example set by teachers in church-run educational institutions. In Strydom,<br />

the church's position reflects the Aristotelian (or aretaic) view that moral<br />

virtue is not simply taught, but is acquired by pupils through their<br />

association with teachers who are themselves virtuous, with the corollary<br />

that it is wrong to place pupils with teachers who are not virtuous, because<br />

pupils might thereby be led to conclude that non-virtuous conduct<br />

(including active homosexuality, from the church's perspective) is morally<br />

acceptable. 126 It is in the light of such a theory that the church's concern<br />

makes sense, that its teachers should be role models (in the sense of leading<br />

exemplary Christian lives) and that Strydom's homosexual lifestyle would<br />

set a bad example to students. In the Aristotelian conception, teachers<br />

teach moral values not didactically, as in the case of arithmetic, but<br />

through example. In <strong>this</strong> view, it makes no sense to say, as does Basson J,<br />

that the church's concern about Strydom's setting a bad example is<br />

misplaced because there was no evidence that he wanted to influence<br />

students. 127 Irrespective of his intention not to influence students in<br />

matters of sexuality, in the Aristotelian view his example is itself<br />

influential. As Basson J acknowledges, it is not far-fetched to view<br />

Strydom as a ‘mentor of the students on a personal ... level’. 128 A mentor,<br />

according to the OED, is someone who ‘acts as a guide and adviser to<br />

another person, especially one who is younger and less experienced’.<br />

Strydom's position might not have been one of a spiritual or religious<br />

leader or instructor, but as a mentor who acts as guide and adviser to those<br />

younger and less experienced, it is hard to accept Basson J's contention<br />

(reflected in (5) above) that, at least in relation to his pupils, he ‘was not in<br />

a position of leadership’. 129<br />

Courts appear to have accepted that teachers exert an influence over<br />

pupils not only through the advice or instruction they give, but also in<br />

virtue of the example they set. As the Canadian Supreme Court observed<br />

in Ross v New Brunswick School District No 15, 130 ‘[t]eachers occupy positions<br />

of trust and confidence, and exert considerable influence over their<br />

students as a result of their positions’. 131 The Court quotes Canadian legal<br />

academic Allison Reyes: 132<br />

Teachers are a significant part of the unofficial curriculum because of their<br />

status as ‘medium’. In a very significant way the transmission of prescribed<br />

126<br />

For a version of <strong>this</strong> view of moral virtue, see I Scheffler Of human potential: An essay in<br />

the philosophy of education (1985).<br />

127 Strydom (n 8 above) para 22.<br />

128<br />

As above.<br />

129 As above.<br />

130 [1996] 1 SCR 825.<br />

131<br />

Ross (n 130 above) para 43 (my emphasis).<br />

132 As above.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!