04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CHAPTER<br />

2<br />

THE CONTENT AND<br />

JUSTIFICATION OF<br />

RATIONALITY REVIEW<br />

Alistair Price*<br />

1 Introduction<br />

It is a general principle of South African constitutional law that every law and<br />

every exercise of public power should not be arbitrary but, instead, should be<br />

rational. 1 This principle, developed by the Constitutional Court in a series<br />

of judgments, 2 sets rationality or non-arbitrariness as a necessary condition<br />

that every law or act of all branches and spheres of the state must satisfy in<br />

order to be legally valid. It operates as a minimum standard – a constitutional<br />

baseline – that applies even in circumstances where no fundamental right or<br />

other constitutional standard is directly applicable. By developing <strong>this</strong> principle,<br />

the courts have asserted a significant power, for they are now able to assess,<br />

on substantive grounds, the rationality of every provision in the statute book<br />

and all conduct of the executive, public administration, and other organs of<br />

state.They do so, in general, by deciding whether the law or conduct in<br />

* BBusSc LLB (UCT) BCL (Oxon). Research student, Gonville and Caius College,<br />

Cambridge University. I am very grateful to Michael Bishop, Coel Kirkby, Hannah<br />

Woolaver, and the participants at a seminar on 6 July 2009 at the South African<br />

Institute for Advanced Constitutional, Public, Human Rights and International Law,<br />

Johannesburg, for their comments on an earlier draft of <strong>this</strong> essay. Any errors are mine<br />

alone.<br />

1 Throughout <strong>this</strong> essay, I refer to <strong>this</strong> general prohibition on arbitrariness as the ‘rationality<br />

principle’ and describe its application by the courts as ‘rationality review’.<br />

2<br />

S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 (CC) para 156; Prinsloo v Van der Linde 1997 3 SA 1012<br />

(CC) para 24; New National Party v Government of South Africa 1999 3 SA 191 (CC) paras<br />

19 & 24; Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa: In re Ex parte President of<br />

South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC) paras 85 & 90; United Democratic Movement v President of<br />

South Africa (No 2) 2003 1 SA 495 (CC) para 55; Affordable Medicines Trust v Minister of<br />

Health 2006 3 SA 247 (CC) paras 74 - 79; Albutt v Centre for the Study of Violence and<br />

Reconciliation [2010] ZACC 4 para 49; Poverty Alleviation Network v President of South Africa<br />

[2010] ZACC 5 para 65; Law Society of South Africa v Minister for Transport [2010] ZACC<br />

25 paras 32 - 39; and Glenister v President of South Africa [2011] ZACC 6 paras 55 - 70. For<br />

a comparative analysis of Poverty Alleviation Network and Albutt, see A Price ‘Rationality<br />

review of legislation and executive decisions’ (2010) 127 SALJ 580 - 591. Due to time and<br />

spatial constraints, I have been unable to include a discussion of Law Society of South<br />

Africa and Glenister. Fortunately, the reasoning and outcome of those decisions is<br />

consistent with, and in many respects confirms, the arguments advanced below.<br />

37

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!