04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

344 Chapter 15<br />

The second problem is the response of the legal philosopher to the<br />

recognition that the inheritance of a common world does not forestall error.<br />

(Nor need it!) For while we are indeed endowed with a broad array of<br />

mutually-supporting beliefs, theories, conditions and standards, we cannot<br />

claim that <strong>this</strong> inheritance is a seamless whole, that all our beliefs are true.<br />

Only a hopelessly naïve epistemologist would entertain such a proposition. As<br />

Donald Davidson notes: ‘Error is what gives belief its point.’ 6 Across the<br />

broad domain of social practices, however, we can claim to possess ‘endless<br />

true beliefs’. 7 Of course, it does not follow that the practices themselves are<br />

entirely coherent. Our practices, traditions, institutions and truth<br />

propositions are, as Cohen writes:<br />

… the result, not of legislative design by a single acting on behalf of a coherent<br />

system of values, but of conflicts among individuals acting on behalf of<br />

diverse values and ambitions. And unlike the produce of a supreme legislative<br />

design, the outcomes of such a history are not likely to be a set of coherent<br />

social practices that completely conform to a single scheme of values. 8<br />

The problem with the theorist who reifies theory is that she mistakes these<br />

‘faults, fizzures and heterogeneous layers’ within a practice as a problem<br />

with the practice – and its usefulness – as a whole. Take for example,<br />

Einstein’s contributions to the birth of both relativity theory and quantum<br />

mechanics. No working physicist argues that Einstein’s views were wrong<br />

– in the main – about either basis for modern physics. And yet, on particular<br />

points, Einstein’s views about both have been proven incorrect.<br />

The third form of bewitchment, as Wittgenstein would have it in many<br />

of his ‘just so’ stories, is that we first form theories and then test these<br />

theories against experience. (Not so says Wittgenstein.) It is essential that<br />

we get our order of priority straight. Once a practice is established (through<br />

trial and error), we might wish, upon reflection, to test its assumptions<br />

through experiments that do or do not confirm aspects of the practice’s<br />

usefulness. But that is not how those who reify theory operate. Think again<br />

about Wittgenstein’s various aperçu:<br />

Whence comes the idea that the beginning of a series is a visible section of rails<br />

invisibly laid to infinity? And infinitely long rails correspond to the unlimited<br />

application of a rule (para 218) ... But if something of <strong>this</strong> sort were the case,<br />

how would it help? No; my description only made sense if it was to be<br />

understood symbolically – I should have said: This is how it strikes me ... The<br />

word ‘agreement’ and the word ‘rule’ are closely related to one another, they<br />

are cousins. If I teach anyone the use of the one word, he learns the use of the<br />

other with it (para 224) ... and they agree in the language they use. That is not<br />

agreement in opinions but in a form of life (para 241) ... If language is to be a<br />

6 D Davidson ‘Thought and talk’ in Inquiries into truth and interpretation (1984) 155 168.<br />

7 As above.<br />

8<br />

J Cohen ‘Review: Michael Walzer’s Spheres of justice’ (1986) 83/8 The Journal of Philosophy 457<br />

465.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!