04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

42 Chapter 2<br />

Since New National Party, the rationality principle has been applied to<br />

statutes outside the context of sections 9(1) and 19 on several occasions. 18<br />

In United Democratic Movement v President of South Africa (No 2), 19 the<br />

Constitutional Court unanimously rejected an argument that a legislative<br />

scheme permitting members of Parliament and the provincial legislatures to<br />

change parties without losing their seats during prescribed periods was<br />

arbitrary. The Court held that legislators’ motives when voting for legislation<br />

were irrelevant to rationality review, 20 and that the scheme was rationally<br />

connected to the legitimate purpose of allowing floor-crossing – a purpose<br />

specifically contemplated by the Constitution itself. 21 In Merafong Demarcation<br />

Forum v President of South Africa, 22 the Court applied the rationality<br />

principle to those provisions of the Constitution Twelfth Amendment Act 23<br />

that purported to alter provincial boundaries so that the Merafong City Local<br />

Municipality, which initially lay partly in Gauteng and partly in the North West<br />

province, would be located entirely within North West. Remarkably, all the<br />

justices appeared to agree that it was appropriate to apply the rationality<br />

principle, not only to the provisions of the Act, but also to the prior decision of<br />

the Gauteng provincial legislature to approve the Bill, as part of the legislative<br />

process in terms of sections 74(3)(b) and (8) of the Constitution. 24 Both<br />

18 Further examples, in addition to those discussed in the text, are Affordable Medicines (n 2<br />

above) paras 74 - 77, 96 - 100; Poverty Alleviation Network (n 2 above) paras 64 - 76; Law<br />

Society of South Africa (n 2 above) paras 32 - 33; Glenister (n 2 above) paras 55 - 70.<br />

19 n 2 above.<br />

20<br />

United Democratic Movement (n 2 above) para 56.<br />

21 United Democratic Movement (n 2 above) paras 57-5 & 69 - 75. The enactment of floorcrossing<br />

legislation is envisaged by item 23A(3) of Annexure A to Schedule 6 of the<br />

Constitution.<br />

22 2008 5 SA 171 (CC). Poverty Alleviation Network (n 2 above) concerned a rationality<br />

23<br />

24<br />

challenge to very similar legislation and the Court followed its decision in Merafong.<br />

Of 2005.<br />

The dissenting justices, Moseneke DCJ, Madala and Sachs JJ, all agreed that the decision<br />

of the provincial legislature was irrational, because it acted ‘without a proper appreciation of<br />

its [Constitutional] powers and duties’ (para 124). Van der Westhuizen J doubted in his<br />

joint-majority judgment whether <strong>this</strong> extension of rationality review was appropriate (paras<br />

72 - 74), but nevertheless concurred with the joint-majority judgment of Ngcobo J, who<br />

held that although it was generally undesirable for courts to speculate about what reasons<br />

move legislators to enact laws, the decision of the Gauteng legislature in question was<br />

different. It could appropriately be reviewed for rationality, because it was not ordinary<br />

legislating and the record contained a committee report setting out some reasons for<br />

supporting the Bill which the legislature ‘adopted’ by majority vote (paras 254 - 258).<br />

This extension of rationality review is problematic, for two reasons. First, it is not merely<br />

difficult, but impossible, to tell what reasons subjectively moved legislators to vote for or<br />

against a Bill. As a collective body, there is no single set of reasons that subjectively moves all<br />

the legislators when they vote. That is so even where, as here, the majority of the legislature<br />

adopts a document setting out the reasons for a Bill which satisfied a legislative committee.<br />

For the committee and the legislature are different bodies and legislators are not constrained<br />

to follow the reasoning of committee members. This is borne out by Moseneke DCJ’s<br />

observation (para 176) that there were four possible sources of reasons for the Gauteng<br />

legislature’s decision to approve the Bill, which were not all consistent. What justified his<br />

relying only on one source of reasons, while disregarding the others (para 176)? The<br />

extension also appears to conflict with the unanimous ruling in United Democratic Movement<br />

(n 2 above) that legislative motives are irrelevant to rationality review (para 56). Secondly, it<br />

is impossible to conceive of some non-fictional, objective set of reasons that moved every<br />

legislator in his or her legislative voting. It surely follows that empowering courts to review

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!