04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

342 Chapter 15<br />

1 Introduction<br />

The way the vast majority of us (legal academics in South Africa) think<br />

about the relationships between legal theory and legal practice is<br />

dramatically out of step with what the majority of (non-legal)<br />

philosophers, neuroscientists, cognitive psychologists, economists, and<br />

other behavioural researchers have to say about the relationship between<br />

theory and practice. One consequence of these erroneous views is that the<br />

manner in which the majority of us understand ‘theory’ – as a metaphysical<br />

term – is sharply at odds with how things actually are. We replicate similar<br />

kinds of errors when we think about how various forms of life, ways of<br />

being in the world or social practices are constructed and how change<br />

actually occurs within such practices. Once again, epistemological fallacies<br />

with regard the role of legal theory have the consequence of leading us to<br />

reify legal theory in a manner that closer inspection shows to be<br />

unwarranted. This second error (‘the reification of theory’) leads many a<br />

legal academic to offer theoretical critiques at odds with what we know<br />

about the human condition and of limited value with regards to the<br />

reconstruction of the form of life we call ‘law’.<br />

Advocates and attorneys in South Africa know something legal<br />

academics often forget: Practice and theory work hand in glove. For the<br />

most part, theory is understood as therapy for practice and they endorse<br />

the Wittgensteinian proposition that [legal] ‘philosophy is a battle against<br />

the bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language’. 1 What they are<br />

aware of – consciously or not – is that we often mistakenly speak of the<br />

social practices, endowments and associations that make up our lives as if<br />

we were largely free to choose them or make them up as we go along. We<br />

are not. As Walzer argues, there is a ‘radical givenness’ to our social world<br />

and the practices that make it up. 2 What he means, in short, is that most of<br />

the practices that make up our social life are involuntary. We do not<br />

choose our family. We generally do not choose our race or religion or<br />

ethnicity or nationality or class or citizenship. More to the point – we<br />

rarely choose or even influence the legal system that controls part of our<br />

social life. Moreover, even when we appear to have the space to exercise<br />

choice, we rarely create the practices within which we participate. The<br />

vast majority of our practices and forms of life are already there, culturally<br />

determined entities that pre-date our existence or, at the very least, our<br />

recognition of the need for them. Finally, even when we overcome inertia<br />

and do create some new practice (and let me not be understood to<br />

underestimate the value of such overcoming and creativity), the very<br />

structure and style of the practice is almost invariably based upon an<br />

existing rubric. So gay marriages may be truly new – but marriage itself is a<br />

1 L Wittgenstein Philosophical investigations (1945) (1953) para 109.<br />

2<br />

M Walzer ‘On involuntary association’ in A Gutmann (ed) Freedom of association (1998)<br />

64 67.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!