04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

378 Chapter 16<br />

Though Rawls sought to apply <strong>this</strong> method to the realm of political<br />

philosophy, in our view, it also seems peculiarly apposite to law. Indeed,<br />

we contend that it provides a better account than the notion of ‘justificatory<br />

ascent’ of the relation between abstract theory and the concrete practice of<br />

adjudication. Ultimately, legal theory and doctrine help develop the<br />

approach that should be adopted in concrete judgments, and concrete<br />

judgments help test whether the legal theory or principles we hold are the<br />

correct ones. This idea does not create an interminable regress to greater<br />

levels of abstract theory for it is about obtaining a ‘fit’ between abstract<br />

theory and concrete judgments. Moreover, it recognises the non-linear<br />

nature of legal justification which is about a backward and forward<br />

movement between the abstract and the concrete and a web of interlocking,<br />

supporting considerations. 44<br />

This account also helps explain why theory and practice in law are<br />

inevitably intertwined. And why an attempt to eschew one or the other in<br />

adjudication will be unsound. 45 In the next section, we look at the notion of<br />

minimalism which attempts largely to reduce the role of theory in<br />

adjudication. Our abstract discussion thus far supports Woolman’s critique of<br />

minimalism which we bolster with a consideration of a set of concrete cases as<br />

well.<br />

Part 2: Minimalism<br />

Minimalism has been formulated in a rather extreme way by the South<br />

African Constitutional Court in the case of Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei. In<br />

<strong>this</strong> case, the Court stated that judges should never ‘formulate a rule broader<br />

than is required by the precise facts to which it is to be applied’. 46 This<br />

statement is, however, clearly too strong and in fact incoherent in that a rule<br />

must always necessarily be broader than the actual situation out of which it<br />

arises. 47 Nevertheless, what is evident is the Court’s desire to avoid general<br />

theoretical engagement. This approach led to certain early critiques of the<br />

Court as having provided South Africa with a vague and rather superficial<br />

‘rainbow jurisprudence’. 48<br />

Currie wrote a defence of the Constitutional Court’s method of<br />

proceeding which essentially involved defending a minimalist approach<br />

44<br />

In epistemological terminology, <strong>this</strong> is more of a coherence than a foundationalist<br />

theory. For an impressive defence of a coherence theory of justification in epistemology,<br />

see BonJour The structure of empirical knowledge (1988).<br />

45<br />

It should also be evident that our approach neither reifies theory nor requires a ‘theory<br />

of everything’ and thus is not subject to the critique entered into by Woolman against<br />

theorists who he claims in his introduction make these mistakes.<br />

46<br />

Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei 1995 4 SA 615 para 8.<br />

47 A rule usually has general application and its application is not confined to particular<br />

persons at particular points of time. The rule of law would be impossible without such a<br />

conception of a legal rule or principle.<br />

48 Cockrell (n 5 above).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!