04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Theory, practice and the legal enterprise 379<br />

to adjudication. 49 In his article, Currie draws on the work of Cass Sunstein<br />

who has defended a minimalist practice recognising the virtues of<br />

‘incompletely theorised agreements’. 50 The insight is that people may be<br />

able to agree on particular decisions without being able to agree on a<br />

broader or abstract theory. ‘It is important because it is a way of promoting<br />

stability, reducing strains on time and capacities, and demonstrating mutual<br />

respect: it is not very respectful to take on other people’s most fundamental<br />

commitments when it is not necessary to do so’. 51 Sunstein attempts to<br />

sidestep any reference to more abstract principles by stipulating an<br />

interpretive methodology based largely on the use of analogy, which he<br />

claims would not require very abstract thinking.<br />

However, Dworkin has pointed out the error in <strong>this</strong> method of proceeding:<br />

there can be no comparison without reference to an external point. Thus, for<br />

instance, and in spite of the popular proverb, one can in fact compare apples and<br />

pears provided one chooses an appropriate point of reference such as colour,<br />

taste or nutritional value. 52<br />

What forms an appropriate external point of reference, of course, then<br />

depends on a broader theory of the purposes of the comparison. 53 Woolman<br />

points out that while Sunstein shows significant ambivalence towards theorising<br />

in judgments, he is forced to concede the inevitable importance of abstract<br />

principles in adjudication. 54 In our view, Roederer has correctly argued that,<br />

at the end of day, the difference between Dworkin and Sunstein is one of<br />

attitude. 55 Dworkin ultimately accepts that conceptual ascent may be limited to<br />

those instances where it is necessary. 56 Similarly, Sunstein accepts the necessity<br />

of a degree of theory and has toned down his views on minimalism to become<br />

a ‘presumption, or a mood and not a rule’. 57<br />

We have argued in the last section that there are layers of theory in the<br />

law. Judicial practice involves moving backwards and forwards between<br />

these different layers to arrive at a justifiable decision in the circumstances of<br />

a particular case. By eschewing abstract theory, a minimalist procedure<br />

removes judges from considering some of the necessary elements involved in<br />

49 Currie (n 2 above).<br />

50 See, eg, C Sunstein One case at a time (1996); C Sunstein ‘Incompletely theorised<br />

agreements in constitutional law’ John M Olin Working Paper no 322 available at<br />

http://www.law.uchicago.edu/ lawecon/index.html (accessed 20 September 2010);<br />

C Sunstein ‘From theory to practice’ (n 23 above) 389.<br />

51<br />

Sunstein ‘Incompletely theorised agreements’ (n 48 above) 392.<br />

52 Dworkin elaborates upon in <strong>this</strong> in Justice in robes (n 1 above) 69.<br />

53 Sunstein apparently accepts <strong>this</strong> in ‘Incompletely theorised agreements’ (n 48 above)<br />

17 - 18.<br />

54 Woolman (n 5 above) 357 - 358. Sunstein admits in ‘Incompletely theorised<br />

agreements’ (n 48) that ‘any assessment of facts is theory-laden: As Dworkin rightly<br />

stresses, we do not know what and how facts count unless we have a “normative<br />

account”’ (396).<br />

55 Roederer (n 2 above) 510 - 512.<br />

56<br />

Dworkin (n 20 above) 376.<br />

57 Sunstein ‘From theory to practice’ (n 23 above) 402.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!