04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

52 Chapter 2<br />

of powers. 65 It is important to realise that what the principle of comity<br />

requires of courts varies with the circumstances. 66 For the moment, however,<br />

we must consider what the principle of comity requires in the context of<br />

rationality review. Bishop seems to argue that the duty implies that judges<br />

should exercise no discretion at all. As he puts it:<br />

If the test permitted or required judges to use their own discretion in<br />

determining the rationality of a choice, that command [ie the command not to<br />

second-guess legislative choices] would be undermined as judges’ attitudes<br />

would pollute the so-called neutral inquiry. The traditional underpinnings of<br />

rational basis review therefore demand a test that forces predictable outcomes<br />

and removes personal discretion. Judges are therefore obliged to frame the<br />

rational basis test as excluding their discretion. 67<br />

It seems to me that <strong>this</strong> interpretation of what the principle of comity requires<br />

in the context of rationality review is too strict for two connected reasons.<br />

First, it renders rationality review incoherent by sheer definitional stipulation.<br />

For it is beyond doubt, as Bishop convincingly argues, that the application of<br />

the rationality principle often involves the exercise of judicial discretion. This,<br />

as I have explained, is due to the evaluative nature of its purpose requirement<br />

and the vagueness of its effect requirement. 68 Rationality review inevitably<br />

contradicts the duty not to ‘second-guess’ the decisions of the legislature and<br />

executive if that duty is interpreted strictly, as Bishop does, to exclude<br />

discretion altogether.<br />

But, secondly, we need not interpret the duty so strictly: there is<br />

an alternative interpretation that avoids Bishop’s stark conclusions.<br />

Because the rationality principle requires only that the law or conduct in<br />

question serve one acceptable purpose, it envisages a range of rational<br />

laws and acts even wider than that of reasonable laws and acts. Within that<br />

broad range of rational options, the political branches of the state are free<br />

to choose without constraint. Courts engaging in rationality review have<br />

no role to play in regard to <strong>this</strong> political choice from among rational options.<br />

Thus, on the one hand, it is a requirement of the principle of comity that<br />

judges do not ‘second-guess’ policy decisions within <strong>this</strong> legitimate sphere.<br />

On the other hand, however, courts are obliged to police the boundaries of<br />

that sphere by invalidating any law or conduct that lies outside it. They do<br />

so by applying the rationality principle.<br />

Of course, on every occasion that an applicant mistakenly argues that a<br />

rational law or act is irrational, he or she effectively invites the courts to<br />

violate the principle of comity. That is because, by asking the court to<br />

invalidate rational law or conduct the applicant effectively asks the court to<br />

order the political branches not to choose an option lying within their<br />

65 Endicott (n 61 above) 101 - 104.<br />

66 I consider such variability below, in sec 3.3.<br />

67<br />

Bishop (n 5 above) 27.<br />

68 See the discussion above, from sec 2.3.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!