04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Taking diversity seriously: Religious associations and work-related discrimination 83<br />

Secondly, he seems to think that the right to equality is more<br />

fundamental than the right to freedom of religion in the post-apartheid<br />

constitutional order. He does not make <strong>this</strong> claim explicitly, but it is<br />

strongly implied by what he says: that although freedom of religion is an<br />

‘important’ right, the right to equality is ‘foundational to our constitutional<br />

order’. 35 He quotes Minister of Education v Syfrets Trust Ltd 36 to the effect<br />

that equality is ‘not merely a fundamental right; it is a core value of the<br />

Constitution' that ‘goes to the bedrock of our constitutional architecture'. 37<br />

The claim that the right to equality takes precedence over religious liberty<br />

is also implied in a paragraph that appears to state, in the context of the<br />

balancing exercise, a presumption in favour of equality: 38<br />

The question remains whether the right to religious freedom outweighs the<br />

constitutional imperative that there must not be unfair discrimination on the<br />

basis of sexual orientation. The constitutional right to equality is foundational<br />

to the open and democratic society envisaged by the Constitution. As a<br />

general principle, therefore, the Constitution will counteract rather than<br />

reinforce unfair discrimination on the ground of sexual discrimination.<br />

The trouble with the claim that the right to equality is more fundamental,<br />

34<br />

obligation to submit to the jurisdiction of the Beth Din and to accept its imposition of<br />

the state of cherem (para 35). These obligations are voluntarily assumed by members of<br />

the faith and not coerced. The Court recognised a right, previously recognised in South<br />

African law, of religious organisations to excommunicate individuals in order to<br />

safeguard the tenets of their faith. The court held that the right to freedom of<br />

association includes the freedom to refuse association; it must extend as far as allowing<br />

churches to exclude members who act contrary to their beliefs, rules and<br />

determinations (para 37). Religious organisations are entitled to excommunicate<br />

recalcitrant members to ensure conformity with the rules of the faith, to impose<br />

sanctions for their contravention and to protect the right of other members of the<br />

religion not to associate with nonconformists (paras 40 & 58). The Court's decision in<br />

Taylor is correct: Religious associations should be free to impose their own rules on<br />

members, and although the state cannot punish husbands who disobey these rules,<br />

actions instituted by the church which are intended to put pressure on members to<br />

abide by Jewish law, such as the cherem, are acceptable. The liberal position (which the<br />

judgment reflects) has not progressed much from the view advanced by Locke in his ‘A<br />

letter concerning toleration’ in I Shapiro (ed) Two treatises of government and a letter<br />

concerning toleration (2003 [1689]) 223: The means by which members of churches ‘are<br />

to be kept within their duty, are exhortations, admonitions and advice’. If <strong>this</strong> fails, the<br />

recalcitrant individual may be excommunicated: ‘This is the last and most utmost force<br />

of ecclesiastical authority: No other punishment can thereby be inflicted, than that the<br />

relation ceasing between the body and the member which is cut off, the person so<br />

condemned ceases to be a part of that church.’ Locke continues: ‘No church is bound<br />

by the duty of toleration to retain any such person in her bosom, as after admonition<br />

continues obstinately to offend against the laws of the society. For these being the<br />

condition of communion, and the bond of the society, if the breach of them were<br />

permitted without any animadversion, the society would immediately be thereby<br />

dissolved.’ For a more recent statement of <strong>this</strong> position, see TM Scanlon ‘The difficulty<br />

of tolerance’ in TM Scanlon (ed) The difficulty of tolerance: Essays in political philosophy<br />

(2005) 187 194.<br />

35 Strydom (n 8 above) paras 9 & 10.<br />

36 2006 4 SA 25 (CC).<br />

37<br />

Strydom (n 8 above) para 10.<br />

38 Strydom (n 8 above) para 14.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!