04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

394 Chapter 17<br />

I expect that we will still part ways on application, but that parting to me<br />

seems rather minor – even if that means that I appear incorrigible in my views on<br />

the subject. To the extent that I turn my attention to the problem of thinness, and<br />

the need for the Constitutional Court to model rational discourse, I rely on<br />

three primary sources: (1) the curial and extra-curial writings of three<br />

Constitutional Court judges – Justice Edwin Cameron, Justice (now Emeritus)<br />

Kate O’Regan, Deputy Chief Justice Dikgang Moseneke, and one High Court<br />

Judge – Judge Dennis Davis; (2) the analysis of Constitutional Court doctrine<br />

offered by fellow academics and practitioners – Cora Hoexter, Lilian Chenwi,<br />

Dario Milo, Glenn Penfold, Anton Fagan, Martin Brassey, Jason Brickhill and<br />

Frank Snyckers; and (3) my own rather piecemeal work as a legal ethnographer<br />

who worries that many judges fear constitutional analysis, or do not know<br />

how to handle a constitutional matter, because the Constitutional Court has not<br />

made patently clear the manner in which constitutional claims ought to be<br />

handled. Professor Michelman himself is a source for my argument regarding<br />

the need for greater clarity. In his critique of my position in ‘The amazing,<br />

vanishing Bill of Rights’, Professor Michelman writes:<br />

… I have chosen to devote <strong>this</strong> space to seeing what might be said on the other<br />

side, specifically with regard to NM and Masiya, on behalf of a court that, I<br />

quite agree with Woolman, has left itself with a lot of explaining to do. The<br />

controlling opinions are indeed, as Woolman says ‘thinly reasoned’, if by that<br />

we mean they are insufficiently explained ... In developing [various] claims, I<br />

shall quite openly engage in filling in passages that may strike readers as<br />

excessively indulgent of the Court, if not entirely fanciful. 8<br />

Now, Professor Michelman’s good faith reconstructions of both NM and<br />

Masiya are not fanciful at all. What reconstructions demonstrate –<br />

convincingly enough for me to think again about some of my original<br />

contentions – is the kind of judgment that ‘ought’ to issue from the<br />

Constitutional Court if the Constitutional Court is concerned with (a) being<br />

fully understood by its broad audience of other judges, lawyers, law students<br />

and ordinary South Africans; (b) modelling, in a patient manner, rational<br />

political discourse in a contemporary South Africa sorely lacking in that<br />

domain.<br />

The third reworked ground for agreement flows from my recognition<br />

that Professor Michelman’s critique of my application argument has more<br />

than a little merit. But I have never really denied the strength of <strong>this</strong> account.<br />

I have always admitted the obvious: that a poorly drafted text does not allow<br />

for one clear literal construction. To that extent, I have said that some<br />

interpretations of section 39(2) – such as those muscular realist readings offered<br />

by both Professor Michelman and Professor Currie – cannot simply be ignored<br />

and could, potentially, do the work that I ascribe to other sections of the<br />

constitutional text. However, to the extent that it matters, I stand firm on three<br />

propositions: (a) that clear textual markers support cabining ‘application’ issues<br />

8 F Michelman (n 1 above) 2 - 3 citing Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 1 above) 762 790 n 51.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!