04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

360 Chapter 15<br />

and policies designed to fulfil those constitutional norms. Over time, courts,<br />

state actors and non-state actors will have the opportunity to determine<br />

whether various ‘socio-political experiments’ have achieved the ends set for us<br />

by our basic law (as interpreted by the courts, the legislature, the executive and<br />

non-state actors). We will, in instances of policy failure, also have an<br />

opportunity to decide whether the norms or the ends set by the courts, the<br />

legislature, the executive and non-state actors constitute the best possible gloss<br />

on our basic law. Shared constitutional interpretation relies, less upon a<br />

principled dialogue about norm setting and more on rough and tumble<br />

engagement) between the courts, the co-ordinate branches of government, and<br />

the public that is reflexive, as well as forward and lateral looking.<br />

Second, experimental constitutionalism relies heavily on participatory<br />

bubbles. 45<br />

These bubbles are court-initiated or political structures designed to<br />

ensure that ‘meaningful engagement’ about optimal outcomes takes place. For<br />

example, a court might set out a general normative framework within which<br />

44 how different doctrines operate in practice and maintain the space necessary to make<br />

revision of constitutional doctrines possible in light of new experience and novel demands.<br />

In <strong>this</strong> regard, the Constitutional Court might be understood to engage in norm-setting<br />

behaviour that provides guidance to other state actors without foreclosing the possibility of<br />

other effective safeguards for rights or other useful methods for their realisation. Fourth,<br />

a commitment to shared interpretations ratchets down the conflict between co-ordinate<br />

branches and levels of government. Instead of an arid commitment to separation of<br />

powers and empty rhetorical flourishes about courts engaging in legal interpretation not<br />

politics (Ex parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the<br />

Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 4 SA 744 (CC) paras 26 - 28), courts<br />

are freed of the burden of having to provide a theory of everything and can set about<br />

articulating a general framework within which different understandings of the basic text can<br />

co-exist. Indeed, the courts and all other actors have more to gain from seeing how<br />

variations on a given constitutional norm work themselves out in practice. Put slightly<br />

differently, shared constitutional interpretation creates the space for different actors in<br />

different places or with different briefs to try doing things differently, but constitutionally.<br />

The different means may show us which ways of doing things that are more (or less)<br />

successful. Or the different means may shed new light on – or change our understanding of<br />

– the very constitutional ends the varying strategies seek to promote. See MC Dorf ‘The<br />

domain of reflexive law’ (2003) 103 Columbia LR 384.<br />

45 Whereas a scheme of shared constitutional interpretation introduces an experimentalist<br />

element into the upper tiers of government institutions, the physical metaphor of bubbles is<br />

meant to convey three qualities of experimentation and engagement in smaller-scale<br />

institutional processes. First, processes of deliberation are a natural part of ongoing social<br />

interactions. They originate when challenges to a given institutional authority accumulate<br />

and finally come to a boil: just as bubbles form after pressure builds up and escape to the<br />

surface of a liquid. Second, bubbles are meant to suggest limits on the scope of<br />

deliberation. Bubbles only enclose a small amount of space – both in terms of the issues<br />

debated and the number of participants. Third, bubbles are ephemeral. After satisfactory<br />

resolutions emerge from processes of participatory deliberation, the raison d’être for such<br />

processes ceases to exist. Participants can return to their more routine lives. Fourth,<br />

experimentalists recognise that deliberation does not, necessarily, lead to better outcomes.<br />

It can, quite often, lead to a greater polarisation of positions. See S Sturm ‘The promise<br />

of participation’ (1993) 78 Iowa LR 981; C Sunstein Infotopia (2007). Both S Sturm and<br />

C Sunstein note how deliberation can lead, over time, to greater discord and less accurate<br />

decisions – for a variety of reasons: from the ‘big dog’ problem to a propensity toward<br />

‘group-think’. Even deliberative democrats recognise such limits without sensing a need to<br />

forsake deliberation. See A Gutmann and D Thompson Democracy and disagreement (1996).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!