04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The relationship between theory and practice across forms of life 343<br />

long-standing publicly-recognised institution for carrying on intimate or<br />

familial relationships. Even in times of radical transformation, reiteration<br />

and mimicry of existing social practices is the norm.<br />

A reader might want to stop and say, ‘But wait, isn’t Tiger Woods talking<br />

about how theory is altering his practice in the quote above?’ Yes. That’s<br />

true. But to a point. And a very limited one. When the greatest golfer ever to<br />

play the game talks about theory and change, he is talking about what it<br />

means for someone who has already mastered the finest points of the game<br />

(after over 35 years of practice) to make incremental modifications designed to<br />

improve his ball striking. Everyone knows that you can read the entire oeuvre<br />

of golf literature, and never get the ball in the air. Coaches are for Woods<br />

what Wittgenstein’s philosophers are to other discursive practices – aids<br />

against bewitchment. It might feel to Woods, at any given moment, that he is<br />

doing things correctly. But it takes the trained and patient eye of another (his<br />

coach) to spot the tiny variations that make all the difference between a good<br />

swing and a bad one.<br />

While I do not wish to diminish the contributions of fellow members of<br />

South Africa’s legal academy, it seems to me that we – and I include myself –<br />

often get the relationship between theory and practice back to front. To some<br />

extent, our betters and predecessors, such as Ronald Dworkin, are responsible<br />

for <strong>this</strong> mistake. From Taking rights seriously, to Law’s empire to Law’s domain,<br />

Dworkin has laid out modernity’s deepest and broadest theory of law,<br />

generally, and of constitutional law, in particular. General bewitchment by<br />

Dworkin’s project hardly comes as a surprise. 3<br />

The first problem, as Dewey pointed out, is that Dworkin (and those<br />

legal philosophers who emulate him) have ‘arrogated to [themselves] the<br />

office of demonstrating the existence of a transcendent, absolute or inner<br />

reality and revealing to man the nature and features of <strong>this</strong> ultimate and<br />

higher reality’. 4 As Wittgenstein and Heidegger note (as per the quotes<br />

above), no such transcendent, higher reality exists. The practice, and our<br />

ability to master it, comes first. 5<br />

Only subsequent to mastery may we indulge in critique.<br />

3<br />

That a constitutional theory must be a theory of ‘everything’ may still attract a certain<br />

following, but my sense is that most serious contemporary constitutional law scholars<br />

would now reject that proposition. See LH Tribe Constitutional choices (1988) (‘My<br />

reply to the grim metamorphosis of constitutional argument ... into instrumental<br />

calculations of utility or, as pseudo-scientific calibrations ... in which the “costs” ... are<br />

supposedly “balanced” against the “benefits” ... is not to propose an alternative<br />

method ... My reply is to question all formulas as concealing the constitutional choices<br />

that we must make – and that we cannot responsibly pretend to derive from any neutral<br />

method.’)<br />

4<br />

J Dewey Reconstruction in philosophy (1920) 23.<br />

5 Wittgenstein (n 2 above) (para 150) (‘mastery’ of a technique.)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!