04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Does transformative constitutionalism require the recognition of animal rights? 181<br />

characteristics do not seem relevant to the provision of certain types of<br />

protections. 33 The fact that a mentally ill individual may lack moral autonomy<br />

or self-consciousness does not mean that such an individual lacks the<br />

capacity to experience pain or emotions or social connections. Generally,<br />

we recognise that such mentally-ill individuals have certain rights: rights not<br />

to be subjected to pain, rights to express their emotions, rights to enable them<br />

to live lives that are able to express their social bonds. This must mean that<br />

having moral autonomy or self-consciousness is not necessary for having<br />

certain rights. If <strong>this</strong> be the case, and capacities to experience pleasure and<br />

pain, an emotional life, and/or social bonds provide the underlying grounds<br />

for possessing such rights, then it is unclear why non-human animals who<br />

have these characteristics are not equally entitled to such rights. 34 The denial<br />

of such rights to non-human animals would only be justifiable if there were<br />

some good reason to do so. Yet, the only reason appears to be the intuition<br />

of some individuals that they are non-human. Yet, that comes down<br />

ultimately to an arbitrary preference for the human without any grounding<br />

in the actual nature of the beings in question. 35<br />

If the Constitution were to include an arbitrary preference for the human<br />

without any sufficient justification, then it will simply reproduce the moral<br />

failings underlying apartheid in relation to a different group (those who are<br />

not human). This would fail to realise the Constitution’s promise as a<br />

transformative document, designed to place future South African society on a<br />

different and better moral foundation.<br />

The Constitution must therefore be interpreted in such a way as to avoid<br />

<strong>this</strong> severe moral blunder. 36 Currently, as it stands, the Constitution provides<br />

no express protections to non-human animals. The common law has<br />

traditionally classified animals as being forms of property who lack the<br />

33<br />

They are obviously relevant to some kinds of protections such as those relating to<br />

freedom of expression, association and religion.<br />

34 This is a version of what may be termed ‘the argument from marginal cases’. The<br />

argument is found in a variety of literature on the subject: Examples include P Singer<br />

Animal liberation (1995) 16 - 20 and P Cavalieri The animal question (2001) 76.<br />

35 These issues raise the question often posed in philosophy of the characteristics that ground<br />

‘moral status’. T Metz ‘For the sake of friendship: Relationality and relationship as<br />

grounds for beneficence’ (2010) Theoria 54 - 76 suggests a theory – a form of ‘relational<br />

theory of moral status’ – that grounds moral status in relational properties that exist in<br />

the world rather than in certain intrinsic properties. It is not clear whether relational<br />

properties are fundamental and can ground a satisfactory view of moral status; even if<br />

they could, it is unclear that they do so in such a way as to include all and only humans.<br />

A full critique of <strong>this</strong> view lies beyond the scope of <strong>this</strong> paper.<br />

36 This follows from the purposive and contextual approach adopted by the<br />

Constitutional Court. Metz, in his response to <strong>this</strong> article, (T Metz ‘Animal rights and<br />

the interpretation of the South African constitution’ in S Woolman & D Bilchitz (eds) Is<br />

<strong>this</strong> seat taken? Conversations at the Bar, the bench and the academy about the South African<br />

Constitution (2012) 209 claims that my interpretive approach fails to respect certain<br />

principles of ‘formal justice’ such as the ‘fit’ requirement that Dworkin elaborates. This<br />

means that interpretations need to be based upon political principles that make sense of<br />

the ‘recent history of their legal systems as a whole’ and are consonant with formal<br />

features of the system such as precedent. I shall raise two main points in response:<br />

First, the ‘fit’ requirement needs to be understood in the context of South African

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!