04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

272 Chapter 12<br />

priority in reasoning related to constitutional law. This problem seems to<br />

flow from the fact that Alexy rejects the notion that the concept of a principle<br />

is to be tied closely to the notion of an individual right; 25 rather, he seems to<br />

recognise that there are other types of normative considerations that also find<br />

expression in principles (or norms that can be optimised). No differentiation is<br />

made between principles that give expression to rights and those that give<br />

expression to other normative considerations. Where principles clash,<br />

‘[c]ourts should assess the relative weight of these … and resolve the conflict in<br />

favour of the stronger reason’. 26 The worry of these critics is that <strong>this</strong> process<br />

will devalue rights and lead them simply to become one consideration to be<br />

weighed against many others; <strong>this</strong> process may also lead rights not to be<br />

accorded their proper weight in relation to other considerations. As Mattias<br />

Kumm points out, ‘[r]ights and policies compete on the same plane within the<br />

context of proportionality analysis’. 27 This may lead, for instance, to situations<br />

where rights are overridden where they should not be as they are not accorded<br />

the weight they deserve in the proportionality analysis. 28<br />

Meyerson, for instance, seeks to provide an alternative account of the<br />

way in which rights should be conceived in constitutional analysis. She<br />

distinguishes between making a decision on the balance of reasons – an<br />

approach she suggests is advocated by Alexy – and reasoning on a weighted<br />

balance of reasons.<br />

When reasoning on the balance of reasons, decision makers assign all reasons<br />

the weight which they think they actually deserve. By contrast, when reasoning<br />

on a weighted balance of reasons, some … reasons are artificially assigned a<br />

different weight from the weight they would ordinarily receive … [S]uch an<br />

approach would acknowledge that bills of rights do not exclude<br />

consideration of the public interest, but would also build into rights<br />

adjudication a ‘systematic bias’ against permitting the infringement of<br />

rights. 29<br />

Meyerson proceeds to offer arguments in favour of her approach which she<br />

claims is better able to capture the special priority that must be given to<br />

fundamental rights.<br />

Meyerson’s charge against Alexy seems to be that the structural analysis<br />

of rights he proposes fails to give effect to the substantive normative weight<br />

that rights have. To evaluate whether Meyerson is correct or not, it is<br />

25<br />

Alexy (n 6 above) 66. This is contrary to the position of Ronald Dworkin who conceives<br />

of principles as norms ‘which can be offered as reasons for individual rights’ and<br />

contrasts them with norms which relate to collective interests (‘policies’): See Dworkin<br />

Taking rights seriously (n 10 above) 82 90.<br />

26 Meyerson (n 11 above) 809.<br />

27 Kumm (n 15 above) 142.<br />

28<br />

This is not merely a matter of theoretical concern and is a danger which seems to have<br />

occurred in several cases.<br />

29 Meyerson (n 11 above) 811. A similar though slightly different approach is taken by<br />

I Porat ‘The dual model of balancing: A model for the proper scope of balancing in<br />

constitutional law’ (2006) Cardozo LR 1393.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!