04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

194 Chapter 7<br />

The second factor outlined by the Court is similar to the justification<br />

requirement of any law but the third factor can also have application to<br />

non-human animals. Importantly, the court does not confine a<br />

consideration of the effect of the discrimination to the impact on human<br />

dignity alone, but recognises the possibility that there may be ‘an<br />

impairment of a comparably serious nature’. This aspect of the Constitutional<br />

Court’s jurisprudence widens the scope of what may constitute<br />

unfair discrimination. An interesting implication though is that <strong>this</strong> would<br />

seem to open the possibility that other forms of life may also have worth<br />

and be harmed in a manner comparable to a detrimental effect on human<br />

dignity. Indeed, it would seem clear that many forms of treatment<br />

accorded to animals grant little or no consideration to their interests and so<br />

treat them in a manner not consonant with their worth. These forms of<br />

treatment would appear to be prime candidates for impacting upon animal<br />

interests in a comparably serious manner to an impairment of human<br />

dignity.<br />

The Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence on equality thus contains<br />

within it the resources to extend the protection of the equality and nondiscrimination<br />

clauses of the Bill of Rights to non-human animals. An<br />

important challenge, however, needs to be considered here. It is indeed<br />

conceivable that many people will be prepared to acknowledge my claims<br />

that animals have worth, and are entitled to certain protections. Yet, such<br />

people may contend that animals are not entitled to exactly the same<br />

protections as human beings as their interests do not carry equal moral<br />

weight to those of human beings. Such a line of reasoning may be supported<br />

by the fact that many people have in their mind a ‘Great Chain of Being’,<br />

recognising that some non-human animals have more ‘worth’ than others<br />

with humans at the top of the chain. The problem, such an individual may<br />

claim, is not with recognising the worth of animals but recognising their<br />

equal worth and consequently our being required to grant their interests<br />

equal moral weight. Are there any good grounds to resist such an argument?<br />

In responding to <strong>this</strong> argument, it is important to revert to the<br />

grundnorm requiring us not to treat individuals differently without<br />

adequate reason. Importantly, <strong>this</strong> norm places the presumption firmly<br />

in favour of equal moral weight being given to the interests of differing<br />

individuals. Those wishing to argue for lesser weight to be granted to animal<br />

interests must do more than claim that <strong>this</strong> is what we generally have<br />

thought. For, indeed, the history of claims relating to differential moral<br />

weight being attached to interests has often led to grave forms of injustice,<br />

including those under both the Nazi and apartheid systems. This history<br />

draws our attention to the way in which claims of differential moral status<br />

have been abused and so should make us extremely cautious before<br />

accepting that individuals of different groups are of differential worth<br />

unless there is a convincing case to <strong>this</strong> effect.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!