04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

82 Chapter 3<br />

laws ‘will often have more force than claims deriving from other<br />

associations’. 30<br />

Neither freedom of religion nor associational liberty, however, are<br />

absolute rights. Nor is the right to equality an absolute right. Freedom of<br />

association and religious liberty will sometimes have to give way to the<br />

right to freedom from discrimination. Resolving in a particular case the<br />

question of whether the rights to associational freedom and religious<br />

liberty should prevail over non-discrimination depends on a balance:<br />

whether the state should be permitted ‘to subject religious institutions to<br />

laws that substantially burden those institutions, or even strike at their<br />

heart … depends on the extent of the interference with religious<br />

convictions and the strength of the state's justification’. 31 It is in the nature<br />

of such a proportionality exercise that ‘neither conclusion (to interfere or<br />

not to interfere) can be justified by way of a presumption (for or against<br />

interference)’. 32<br />

3 Equality is not more fundamental than freedom of<br />

religion<br />

In Strydom, Basson J creates the impression that the right to equality is<br />

more fundamental, important and ‘core’ than the rights to freedom of<br />

religion and freedom of association, with the result that the church's claim<br />

is weakened in advance of his carrying out of the balancing exercise. He<br />

does so in two ways. First, he mentions the right to freedom of association<br />

only once, in passing, in a paragraph in which he (correctly) dismisses<br />

Taylor v Kurtstag 33 as unhelpful to the question of how to balance religious<br />

liberty and equality in Strydom – Taylor being concerned with the rights of<br />

a member of a church, rather than a non-member as in Strydom, and not<br />

being a case involving unfair discrimination. 34 His failure to consider the<br />

right to freedom of association more fully and to explicate the content of<br />

<strong>this</strong> right in the present context has the effect of improperly diminishing its<br />

significance, tipping the scales in favour of the right to equality.<br />

30 K Greenawalt ‘Freedom of association and religious association’ in Gutmann (n 16<br />

above) 136.<br />

31<br />

C Sunstein ‘Should sex equality law apply to religious institutions?’ in J Cohen et al<br />

(eds) Is multiculturalism bad for women? (1999) 93.<br />

32 Gutmann (n 16 above) 13.<br />

33<br />

2005 1 SA 362 (W).<br />

34<br />

In Taylor (n 33 above), an orthodox Jew sought to prevent the Beth Din, a Jewish<br />

ecclesiastical court established to resolve disputes between members of the orthodox<br />

Jewish community, from publishing a cherem, a notice excommunicating him from the<br />

faith. Following his divorce, the Beth Din had reached a determination directing him to<br />

pay maintenance in respect of his children. He had failed to abide by the order,<br />

subsequent to which the Beth Din had issued the cherem. The applicant objected to the<br />

<strong>publication</strong> of the cherem on the grounds that it constituted defamation and violated his<br />

right freely to associate with other members of his religious community. The court ruled<br />

that as an orthodox Jew, he was ‘required to comply fully with the dictates of Jewish<br />

law and society and the mandates of Jewish law and ethics’, which include the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!