04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The content and justification of rationality review 69<br />

been problematic. Despite the discretionary character of the test, the<br />

outcomes and reasoning in most cases have been defensible.<br />

5.2 Three difficult cases<br />

Three instances of rationality review by the Constitutional Court deserve<br />

closer scrutiny. All three cases were genuinely difficult, albeit for differing<br />

reasons, so it is not surprising that the Court was divided on each occasion.<br />

I shall supplement my defence of the Constitutional Court’s record by<br />

defending the majority’s application of the rationality principle in the first<br />

and second cases, and by offering an interpretation of the majority judgment<br />

in the third case.<br />

We start with the judgment in Merafong 145 where, to recall, the<br />

Merafong community challenged, inter alia, the rationality of legislation<br />

amending provincial boundaries to relocate the Merafong municipality,<br />

which had previously straddled the Gauteng-North West border, wholly<br />

within North West. The community passionately wanted to be placed in<br />

Gauteng. Everyone agreed that abolishing cross-boundary municipalities<br />

would serve the valuable purpose of promoting effective state service<br />

delivery. But what exactly had to be rational? Was it the decision to abolish<br />

cross-boundary municipalities by relocating Merafong in either Gauteng or<br />

North West? Or the decision to locate Merafong in North West instead of<br />

Gauteng? The choice had a direct bearing on the outcome: the former<br />

characterisation automatically ensured that the law served its purpose and<br />

thus was rational; the latter presumably called for an additional purpose to<br />

be served specifically by choosing North West over Gauteng, but since the<br />

state had not proffered one, and the relative consequences of choosing<br />

either North West or Gauteng were contested and uncertain, the law may<br />

have been arbitrary. 146 This choice of characterisation is a particularly clear<br />

example of the discretion judges must sometimes exercise under the<br />

rationality principle.<br />

The majority chose the former characterisation and upheld the law. 147<br />

In my view, <strong>this</strong> was the correct outcome, for two connected reasons. First,<br />

even under the latter characterisation, the law could not justifiably be<br />

regarded as arbitrary or irrational. Locating Merafong within North West<br />

still served the purpose of abolishing a cross-boundary municipality<br />

thereby easing service delivery problems. It could hardly be said in reply that<br />

defining the purpose at <strong>this</strong> level of abstraction renders rationality review<br />

meaningless. But secondly, as Van der Westhuizen J observed, 148 adopting<br />

the narrower characterisation and investigating whether choosing North<br />

West over Gauteng served legitimate purposes over and above that of<br />

145 n 22 above. Other aspects of the case are discussed above (n 24 above) and 56.<br />

146 This is what I understand Bishop (n 5 above) to imply at 24. He observes that Sachs J had<br />

previously suggested in an obiter dictum in a minority concurring judgment in a similar<br />

case (Matatiele Municipality v President of South Africa (1) 2006 5 SA 47 (CC) paras 101 -<br />

108) that the latter characterisation of the issue was appropriate.<br />

147<br />

n 22 above, para 114. The minority did not address the issue.<br />

148 n 22 above, para 114.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!