04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

224 Chapter 9<br />

famously presented as a formulation of the categorical imperative, is<br />

inseparable from the possibility that each of us can project our ends as a<br />

reasonable creature who can promote a community in which ‘mine’<br />

harmonises with ‘yours’ in the Kingdom of Ends. 4<br />

Negative freedom can entail limiting our own immediate desires<br />

through our attempt to live a purposive life, but it is not simply antagonistic<br />

to needs or desires. As finite beings we must make choices. We cannot be<br />

everywhere at once, and if we did not make choices we would not be able to<br />

represent them as part of our own life project. In <strong>this</strong> specific sense we have to<br />

exercise our prudence. Positive freedom for a creature that must live in a<br />

finite body, bound by the laws of nature, must proceed through a notion of<br />

autonomy that reconciles law and freedom. Indeed, positive freedom for<br />

Kant is causality through moral action, in which each of us potentially<br />

creates a new beginning as a moral person and with other persons, and aspires<br />

to create a new social and political order guided by the Kingdom of Ends.<br />

For Kant, autonomy is not at all reducible to being left alone by others<br />

– not even in a more affirmative sense of aloneness as self-determination. This is<br />

precisely because for Kant freedom must be law-like, which means we exercise<br />

our autonomy not when we are strictly self-determining – true selfdetermination<br />

is beyond the reach of a finite creature for Kant – but rather<br />

when we represent our ends as our own and not merely determined by the<br />

pulls and tugs of the day to day world; in the strongest sense, we can only<br />

hope to attain freedom by imposing a law upon ourselves which allows us to<br />

represent ourselves as the source of a different ethical causality, a new moral<br />

beginning. Negative and positive freedom together, as Kant understands<br />

them, should be taken to mean that it is human beings who set value on ends;<br />

we make them ours in that we project an ‘I’ as a necessary postulate of the very<br />

practical reason to which we must return to justify our ends.<br />

To understand freedom and autonomy in <strong>this</strong> way is extremely<br />

significant for the law of the new South Africa, as the judgments of the<br />

emeritus justice, Justice Ackermann, demonstrate. First, as I have already<br />

suggested, the Kantian notion of positive freedom or autonomy gives us a<br />

defence of equality that does not depend on human persons being materially<br />

alike – a problem that has plagued some theorists in the Anglo-American<br />

academy. Human beings have equal worth because we all have the<br />

4<br />

The concept of every rational being as one who must regard himself as giving universal law<br />

through all the maxims of his will, so as to appraise himself and his actions from <strong>this</strong><br />

point of view, leads to a very fruitful concept dependent upon it, namely that of a<br />

kingdom of ends. By a kingdom I understand a systematic union of various rational beings<br />

through common laws. Now since laws determine ends in terms of their universal<br />

validity, if we abstract from the personal differences of rational beings as well as from<br />

all the content of their private ends we shall be able to think of a whole of all ends in<br />

systematic connection (a whole both of rational beings as ends in themselves and of the<br />

ends of his own that each may set himself), that is, a kingdom of ends, which is possible<br />

in accordance with the above principles’ (Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals (1997)<br />

41).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!