04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Rationaliy is dead! Long live rationality! Saving rational basis review 27<br />

purpose only in some conceivable way then all laws that identify a legitimate<br />

purpose – which we have seen is always possible – will pass the test. This<br />

standard fails to fulfill the requirement that a law must be connected to a<br />

public end because the connection is determined by the ingenuity of<br />

government and lawyers and the discretion of courts, not the effects of the<br />

law; any law can be saved by dreaming up some purpose that it might<br />

theoretically serve. It is only by raising <strong>this</strong> standard that rationality review<br />

can become meaningful. But once the standard is raised to something like<br />

‘a fair and substantial relation’, 129 the test affords judges too much power as<br />

many – maybe even a majority of laws – might reasonably be said not to<br />

‘substantially’ advance their purpose. Courts have not been able to identify a<br />

mid-point that is both meaningful and restrained.<br />

Fourthly, an element of the means-end test is the use of empirical<br />

evidence. If courts refuse to engage it at all, then the test – no matter what<br />

theoretical standard is employed – becomes an armchair game for lawyers<br />

and judges. While the possibility that a law may further a purpose might be<br />

deduced from ‘rational speculation’, 130 the extent to which the purpose is<br />

advanced must rest on empirical facts. 131 Evaluative rationality – the<br />

essence of rational basis review – only makes sense if courts are willing to<br />

examine empirical facts. 132 But if the courts begin to evaluate the relative<br />

worth of competing empirical claims or to make judgments where<br />

empirical knowledge is uncertain, then we must ask: Why do we trust their<br />

judgment in that task more than that of the legislators?<br />

The discretion inherent in the application of the test creates two types of<br />

problems. First, there is a massive gap between the rhetoric of courts which<br />

emphasises the mechanical nature of the test, and the degree of discretion<br />

courts in fact exercise. The lack of transparency is an evil in itself: Courts should<br />

practise what they preach or, more precisely, preach what they practise. It also<br />

reduces certainty. As the American experience demonstrates, courts can apply<br />

variable levels of scrutiny while claiming to adhere to the same standard.<br />

Moreover, it makes life difficult for litigants who cannot explicitly make some<br />

of the arguments that would influence courts, because courts officially deem<br />

those arguments irrelevant. Forcing those arguments into the subtext of<br />

litigation serves nobody. This is not a criticism that is unique to rationality<br />

review; it can and has been made about many areas of law, but it is especially<br />

blatant in the rationality context. Justice Marshall has explicitly commented on<br />

the discrepancy between word and deed, between rhetoric and reality:<br />

129<br />

Royster Guano (n 23 above) 415.<br />

130 Beach Communications (n 20 above) 315.<br />

131 See Bice (n 4 above) 13.<br />

132<br />

As above. (‘The formal elements of evaluation concern the logical pattern of the actor’s<br />

beliefs, namely whether the actor believes that his behaviour will achieve his goals and<br />

whether he believes that his actions will do so efficiently. The empirical elements of<br />

evaluation cannot be satisfied formally; they must be satisfied by reference to an<br />

objective standard outside the actor.’)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!