04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

258 Chapter 11<br />

4 The case for balancing<br />

Missing from Botha and Woolman’s account is the powerful counter-case<br />

in favour of balancing. The case is made in Alexy’s descriptive work on the<br />

practice of the German Constitutional Court, a practice that has been<br />

characterised since the inception of the court by a commitment to the<br />

principle of proportionality and to its sub-principle, balancing. Though<br />

Alexy is cautious about claiming the accuracy of his theoretical<br />

conclusions about the nature of rights adjudication only in relation to the<br />

jurisprudence of the German Court, his account of rights obviously has<br />

more general application to any jurisdiction to which proportionality and<br />

balancing has spread. What, then, is Alexy’s answer to the objections to<br />

balancing that have been set out above?<br />

We need to begin with an overview of Alexy’s argument about the nature<br />

of constitutional rights, as the principle of proportionality and balancing are<br />

necessary attributes of <strong>this</strong> particular conception of rights. One can begin with<br />

Dworkin’s famous debate with Hart about positivism’s ‘model of rules’. 38 Law,<br />

Dworkin showed, consisted of more than just a set of valid legal rules but<br />

contained also ‘standards that do not function as rules, but operate differently<br />

as principles, policies and other sorts of standards’. 39 Dworkin illustrated the<br />

existence and operation of one of these standards – principles – by reference to<br />

the 1889 case of Riggs v Palmer, which posed the question as to whether an heir<br />

named in the will of his grandfather could inherit when he had murdered his<br />

grandfather. 40 The decision entailed the clash of competing legal principles –<br />

namely, that no one should profit from his wrong versus the principle that wills<br />

should be upheld. The result in Riggs was in favour of the first principle, the<br />

murderer did not inherit. But <strong>this</strong> decision did not invalidate the second principle,<br />

which remained good law for use in a future case. This showed, Dworkin<br />

reasoned, that principles were structurally different to rules, lacking the ‘all or<br />

nothing’ quality of the latter and having, instead, a ‘dimension of weight’ which<br />

permitted conflicting principles to be maintained in a legal system without<br />

cancelling each other out:<br />

When principles intersect ... one who must resolve the conflict has to take<br />

into account the relative weight of each. This cannot be, of course, an<br />

exact measurement, and the judgment that a particular principle or policy is<br />

more important than another will often be a controversial one. Nevertheless,<br />

it is an integral part of the concept of a principle that it has <strong>this</strong> dimension, that<br />

it makes sense to ask how important or how weighty it is. 41<br />

Alexy’s work builds from <strong>this</strong> relatively modest foundation a general<br />

classification of constitutional rights norms into rules and principles: ‘the<br />

38 R Dworkin Taking rights seriously (1977).<br />

39 Dworkin (n 38 above) 22.<br />

40<br />

Dworkin (n 38 above) 23.<br />

41 Dworkin (n 38 above) 26 - 27.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!