04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Theory, practice and the legal enterprise 377<br />

circumstances of a case influence the way in which it is justified and the more<br />

abstract principles and theory that result. Yet, abstract theory and higher level<br />

principles also condition the way in which the concrete circumstances are<br />

viewed. 37 This interplay between the concrete and the abstract is a<br />

productive one and a decision is arrived at when congruence exists between<br />

the different levels. The idea is less about a construction where one block is<br />

built upon another; rather, it involves the notion of a network of intersecting<br />

considerations that help justify a concrete decision.<br />

This method of proceeding appears to be very similar to the method of<br />

justification in political philosophy that John Rawls refers to as ‘reflective<br />

equilibrium’. 38 This method requires us first to identify what Rawls terms<br />

certain considered judgments about justice. These are judgments that are<br />

arrived at by considering ‘what one thinks about the question at hand rather<br />

than by consciously applying some principle or theory’. 39 Such judgments<br />

are considered in the sense that they are arrived at under certain conditions:<br />

For instance, individuals will be aware of relevant facts, they are not upset or<br />

frightened, and do not stand to gain or lose by those judgments. 40 They are<br />

also not arbitrary 41 and are stable over time. 42 Ultimately, these considered<br />

judgments place constraints on the theory that we will develop. For instance,<br />

if a moral theory leads to the result that slavery is just, we will rather give up<br />

the theory than the considered judgment that slavery is unjust. Considered<br />

judgments thus help to test theory. Yet, such judgments appear groundless<br />

without some form of justification.<br />

This leads to the desire to formulate certain general principles that can<br />

account for the various judgments we make about concrete cases which<br />

cohere together. In developing those principles, we will find that they do not<br />

immediately capture all our considered judgments. The ambition would be to<br />

obtain a set of principles that can adequately account for all our convictions. In<br />

trying to achieve that ambition, we may formulate particular principles that<br />

provide a compelling account of most of our considered judgments. Such<br />

principles may, however, require us to give up some of these judgments that<br />

are not consistent with the principles. On the other hand, certain considered<br />

judgments may be so firmly held as to lead us to give up a particular set of<br />

principles that cannot adequately account for them. ‘One is then to continue<br />

in <strong>this</strong> way, working back and forth between principles and judgments, until<br />

one reaches a set of principles and a set of judgments between which there is<br />

no conflict. This state is what Rawls calls reflective equilibrium.’ 43<br />

37 The order of priority is also not only from concrete to abstract as Woolman suggests at<br />

3.<br />

38 Rawls Theory of justice (1973) 47.<br />

39 TM Scanlon ‘Rawls on justification’ in SR Freeman (ed) The Cambridge companion to Rawls<br />

(2003) 143 - 144.<br />

40 Rawls (n 38 above) 47 - 48.<br />

41 Rawls (n 38 above) 48.<br />

42<br />

J Rawls Collected papers (2001) 6.<br />

43 Scanlon (n 39 above) 141.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!