04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

408 Chapter 17<br />

For Snyckers, the thinness of the Court’s criminal procedure jurisprudence<br />

– as evident in Molimi, Zuma, Thint (Holdings), Shaik and Zealand<br />

– imposes a different set of costs on a single set of parties: the accused. 43<br />

Although the Constitutional Court certainly got off to a fast start in<br />

protecting the accused with respect to its reverse onus decisions, Snyckers<br />

contends that recent cases suggest a weakening of that resolve. He traces that<br />

weakening to the Court’s preference for determining specific cases in terms of<br />

the balancing of rights and interests rather than in rule generation in terms<br />

of the panoply of criminal procedure protections found in the various<br />

substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights. He writes:<br />

In an adversarial criminal justice system, rules tend to favour the accused. Rules,<br />

when applied strictly, create rights. The fewer the rules, the more likely the<br />

conviction. The longer the view taken by a justice system, the more generous<br />

the system to those at its barrel-end. Due process intrudes upon the immediate<br />

desire to punish with an appeal to the perennial need to be humane. It arrives<br />

at the critical moment, embodying the conscience of society, to spoil the<br />

quenching of the bloodlust at the hanging party ... More often than not, [the<br />

accused’s] salvation will lie in the extent to which he is able to invoke rules,<br />

rights and principles that were created for the benefit of others, for situations<br />

other than his, and for the long-term benefit of society. 44<br />

Naturally, Snyckers continues, the accused will prefer rather uncritical<br />

application of these rules rather than nuanced assessments of the application<br />

of the rule in a particular set of circumstances. But the thwarted desires of the<br />

accused are not what troubles Snyckers here. His concern – highlighted by the<br />

quintet of cases handed down by the Constitutional Court in 2008 (Molimi,<br />

Zuma, Thint (Holdings), Shaik and Zealand) 45 – is that the Court’s reflexive<br />

invocation of society’s interests in fighting crime has a tendency to outweigh<br />

the rights-based or rules-based arguments of the defendant. Or as Snyckers<br />

puts it: ‘Such balancing exercises will tend, in the nature of things, to end badly<br />

for [the defendant].’ 46 And that is so because the Court has a tendency to<br />

engage in hand-waving exercises when it comes to the content of a right – too<br />

often preferring a notional approach to rights analysis (in which the abrogation<br />

of the right is merely assumed) as opposed to a value based rule-generating<br />

43 F Snyckers ‘The flight from rights: Rule aversion in dealing with the criminal process<br />

Molimi, Zuma, Thint (Holdings), Shaik and Zealand’ (2009) 2 Constitutional Court Review<br />

269.<br />

44 Snyckers (n 82 above) 1.<br />

45 S v Molimi 2008 3 608 (CC); Thint v National Director of Public Prosecutions; Zuma v<br />

National Director of Public Prosecutions 2009 1 SA 1; Thint Holdings v National Director<br />

of Public Prosecutions; Zuma v National Director of Public Prosecutions 2009 1 SA 141; S v<br />

Shaik 2008 5 SA 354 (CC); Zealand v Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development<br />

2008 4 SA 458 (CC).<br />

46 Snyckers (n 43 above) 1.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!