04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

276 Chapter 12<br />

will be loaded in favour of rights. What these theorists highlight is rather a<br />

concern about the likelihood that courts (and possibly other institutions)<br />

will not conduct the process of balancing properly and so fail to give rights<br />

the weight they deserve in such a process.<br />

The critique of Alexy thus highlights the importance of ensuring that<br />

the structure of rights analysis is congruent with its purpose. I would<br />

suggest that congruency is not sufficient: The form should itself give<br />

expression to the purpose of rights protection. The worries of Alexy’s<br />

critics in relation to the form of his theory should not be easily dismissed.<br />

The evaluation of rights against other considerations on the same ‘level’<br />

may tend to lead courts to fail to give sufficient strength to rights and thus<br />

lead to their under-protection. It may thus be necessary to develop<br />

procedural safeguards that ensure rights are given the strength they deserve<br />

in any constitutional analysis. The two-stage procedure in South African<br />

constitutional law assists in ensuring that at least courts begin by thinking<br />

through the nature of the violation that occurs in relation to a particular<br />

constitutional right. It is thus critical that courts do not omit the first stage<br />

of the analysis and seek to capture the interests and values at stake in a<br />

particular violation. 41 The second stage of the inquiry will involve a<br />

proportionality analysis which must take account of the ‘nature of the<br />

right’: This factor will require understanding the strength and intensity to<br />

be given to a particular right. 42<br />

Yet, it might be thought that these procedural elements remain<br />

insufficient to deal with the likelihood of error on the part of courts in giving<br />

rights the strength they deserve. Various possibilities suggest themselves: One<br />

has already been canvassed in the form of a presumption in favour of rights.<br />

Alexy suggests another possibility for dealing with the problems identified by<br />

Kumm that would not systematically over-protect rights but, he claims, deal<br />

with the likelihood of error in such cases.<br />

He indicates that these problems arise particularly when empirical<br />

premises lie at the foundation of a claim to limit rights: the proposition, for<br />

instance, that the inclusion of lesbian and gay people in the military impacts<br />

upon its fighting power and effectiveness. Alexy consequently proposes a<br />

second law of balancing to be included within the proportionality analysis:<br />

‘The more heavily an interference in a constitutional right weighs, the<br />

41 I thus support the arguments of Woolman & Botha (n 1 above) 34-18 - 34-29 where<br />

they criticise certain dicta by Justice Sachs that suggest a possible conflation between<br />

the two stages of the inquiry. They also correctly criticise decisions such as Christian<br />

Education where the first stage is virtually entirely omitted. For a recent example of the<br />

majority of the Court failing adequately to conduct the first stage of the analysis, see<br />

Road Accident Fund v Mdeyide 2011 2 SA 26 (CC) and D Bilchitz ‘How should rights be<br />

limited? Road Accident Fund v Mdeyide (2011) Journal of South African Law 568.<br />

42 In the last section, I will suggest why, when we understand the nature of the substantive<br />

enquiry we are to conduct, there would also be a systematic bias in favour of rights<br />

protection.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!