04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Does transformative constitutionalism require the recognition of animal rights? 177<br />

‘[f]rom the outset the country maintained a colonial heritage of racial<br />

discrimination: In most of the country the franchise was reserved for white<br />

males and a rigid system of economic and social segregation was<br />

enforced.’ 15 In describing the central elements of the apartheid system, the<br />

Court states that ‘[r]ace was the basic, all-pervading and inescapable<br />

criterion for participation by a person in all aspects of political, economic<br />

and social life’. 16<br />

Mahomed J (and many of the other judges) recognised <strong>this</strong> as one of the<br />

key facets of South African history that the Constitution was designed to take<br />

us away from<br />

the contrast between the past which it repudiates and the future to which it<br />

seeks to commit the nation is stark and dramatic. The past institutionalised<br />

and legitimised racism. The Constitution expresses in its preamble the need for a<br />

‘new order … in which there is equality between ... people of all races’… The<br />

past was redolent with statutes which assaulted the human dignity of persons<br />

on the grounds of race and colour alone; section 10 constitutionally protects<br />

that dignity. The past accepted, permitted, perpetuated and institutionalised<br />

pervasive and manifestly unfair discrimination against women and persons<br />

of colour; the Preamble, section 8 and the postamble seek to articulate an<br />

ethos which not only rejects its rationale but unmistakenly recognises the<br />

clear justification for the reversal of the accumulated legacy of such<br />

discrimination. 17<br />

It is important to analyse in a little more depth, the reasons why we regard<br />

discrimination on grounds of race as so repugnant. Perhaps the key moral<br />

wrong is that it separates out the treatment afforded to a person from any<br />

morally relevant feature of their being: for instance, black people were subject to<br />

inferior education not on the basis of any lack of ability but simply because<br />

they were black. The system of apartheid thus enshrined into law a form of<br />

moral arbitrariness that separated out the treatment of an individual from<br />

their individual capacities.<br />

As Rachels points out, ‘[f]acts about people often figure into reasons<br />

why they may not be treated in <strong>this</strong> or that way. Adam may be ejected from<br />

the choir because he can’t sing. Betty may be given Prozac because she<br />

is depressed. Charles may be congratulated because he has just gotten<br />

engaged … Notice, however, that a fact that justifies one type of treatment<br />

may not justify a different type of treatment: unless something unusual is<br />

14 availability of economic opportunities.’ I do not seek to deny that other factors<br />

contributed to apartheid such as the economic motivation for cheap labour: Rather,<br />

what I wish to assert here is that a central feature of apartheid was institutionalised<br />

racial discrimination which, at least to some extent, was based upon an ideology of white<br />

supremacy. See De Vos (n 13 above) 14 for a critique of construing the evils of South<br />

African history too narrowly.<br />

15 Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the<br />

Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 4 SA 744 (CC) para 5.<br />

16<br />

Certification judgment (n 15 above) para 7.<br />

17 Makwanyane (n 8 above) para 262.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!