04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Response to Klaaren 445<br />

Furthermore, the characterisation of the issue as ‘ethical’ as opposed to<br />

legal might itself be open to question. In footnote 31, Klaaren sets out the<br />

extract from the SCA judgment in Langa v Hlophe, which provides the basis<br />

for the suggestion that the complaint might be judged negatively from an<br />

ethical point of view. It is notable that the SCA relied on the constitutional<br />

injunction that all organs of state, including the judiciary, must ‘assist and<br />

protect the independence, impartiality, dignity, accessibility and effectiveness<br />

of the judiciary’. This is derived from section 165(4) of the<br />

Constitution, and calls into question drawing a distinction between how<br />

the complaint is viewed ethically and legally for, if the basis for an<br />

argument that the judges’ conduct was ethically questionable was found in<br />

the Constitution, is it not the case that such conduct is therefore also legally<br />

suspect?<br />

Klaaren concludes that judicious transparency can be seen in the<br />

issuing of the Constitutional Court media statement for three reasons: the<br />

importance of the subject matter, because it was a ‘statement by judges<br />

about a judge and about judging’; the fact that it was done by judges and<br />

thus ‘constituted a judicial practice’, rendering the judges potentially liable<br />

for defamation; and in the ‘proper context’, beyond the narrow reasoning<br />

of the SCA, taking into account the role of national intelligence agencies<br />

and constituting ‘a broader attack on judicial independence’. Regarding<br />

the latter ground, Klaaren remarks that ‘[t]his is judicious, appropriately<br />

not as a judicial function, but rather as a non-judicial decision taken by<br />

those entrusted to deciding judicially’. It is unclear how, particularly in<br />

light of the arguments he has been advancing up to <strong>this</strong> point, Klaaren<br />

regards a non-judicial decision as being an example of judicious<br />

transparency. It may suggest, as certain other parts of the paper do, that<br />

what determines judicious transparency is not the nature of the how of<br />

transparency is exercised that makes it judicious so much as the identity of<br />

who is making the transparency decision.<br />

In which case, while perhaps less intellectually stimulating an exercise,<br />

an approach that sought to define the parameters for judicial transparency<br />

– such as openness around interviewing and application for judicial office,<br />

conflicts of interest and private financial holdings – might have made for a<br />

more useful contribution to both the theoretical understanding and<br />

application of the principle of transparency at a time when the demand for<br />

information disclosure as of right is growing and the dangers of secrecy –<br />

in the judiciary as in all sites of public and private power – more and more<br />

obvious.<br />

What might the foundations of such a theory of ‘judicial transparency’<br />

be? It is beyond the scope of <strong>this</strong> paper to develop a detailed theoretical<br />

framework, but some basic components may be identified here (in the hope<br />

that they might provoke further debate and thought). Firstly, the criteria<br />

for judicial appointment ought to be clearly established and openly known.<br />

Despite the JSC having been established under the 1996 Constitution,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!